Introductory Note
Thomas Babington Macaulay (1800-1859) was the son of Zachary Macaulay, a Scotsman
whose experience in the West Indies had made him an ardent Abolitionist. Thomas was an
infant prodigy, and the extraordinary memory which is borne witness to in his writings was
developed at an early age. He was educated at Cambridge, studied law, and began to write
for the "Edinburgh Review" at twenty-five, his well-known style being already
formed. He entered the House of Commons in 1830, and at once made a reputation as an
orator. In 1834 he went to India as a member of the Supreme Council, and during his three
and a half years there he proved himself a capable and beneficent administrator. On his
return, he again entered Parliament, held cabinet office, and retired from political life
in 1856.
Until about 1844 Macaulay's writings appeared chiefly in the "Edinburgh
Review," the great organ of the Whig Party, to which he belonged. These articles as
now collected are perhaps the most widely known critical and historical essays in the
language. The brilliant antithetical style, the wealth of illustration, the pomp and
picturesqueness with which the events of the narrative are brought before the eyes of the
reader, combine to make them in the highest degree entertaining and informing. His
"History of England," which occupied his later years, was the most popular book
of its kind ever published in England, and owed its success to much the same qualities.
The "Lays of Ancient Rome" and his other verses gained and still hold a large
public, mainly by virtue of their vigor of movement and strong declamatory quality.
The essay on Machiavelli belongs to Macaulay's earlier period, and illustrates his
mastery of material that might seem to lie outside of his usual field. But here in the
Italy of the Renaissance, as in the England or the India which he knew at first hand, we
have the same characteristic simplification and arrangement of motives and conditions that
make his clear exposition possible, the same dash and vividness in bringing home to the
reader his conception of a great character and a great epoch.
Machiavelli1
[Footnote 1: Originally published as a review of a translation of the complete works of
Machiavelli by J. V. Peries.]
Part I
Those who have attended to this practice of our literary tribunal are well aware, that,
by means of certain legal fictions similar to those of Westminster Hall, we are frequently
enabled to take cognizance of cases lying beyond the sphere of our original jurisdiction.
We need hardly say, therefore, that, in the present instance, M. Perier is merely a
Richard Roe, who will not be mentioned in any subsequent stage of the proceedings, and
whose name is used for the sole purpose of bringing Machiavelli into court.
We doubt whether any name in literary history be so generally odious as that of the man
whose character and writings we now propose to consider. The terms in which he is commonly
described would seem to impart that he was the Tempter, the Evil Principle, the discoverer
of ambition and revenge, the original inventor of perjury, and that, before the
publication of his fatal "Prince," there had never been a hypocrite, a tyrant,
or a traitor, a simulated virtue, or a convenient crime. One writer gravely assures us
that Maurice of Saxony learned all his fraudulent policy from that execrable volume.
Another remarks, that, since it was translated into Turkish, the sultans have been more
addicted than formerly to the custom of strangling their brothers. Lord Lyttelton charges
the poor Florentine with the manifold treasons of the house of Guise, and with the
Massacre of St. Bartholomew. Several authors have hinted that the Gunpowder Plot is to be
primarily attributed to his doctrines, and seem to think that his effigy ought to be
substituted for that of Guy Fawkes, in those processions by which the ingenuous youth of
England annually commemorate the preservation of the Three Estates. The Church of Rome has
pronounced in works accursed things. Nor have our own countrymen been backward in
testifying their opinion of his merits. Out of his surname they have coined an epithet for
a knave, and out of his Christian name a synonym for the Devil.
It is indeed scarcely possible for any person, not well acquainted with the history and
literature of Italy, to read without horror and amazement the celebrated treatise which
has brought so much obloquy on the name of Machiavelli. Such a display of wickedness,
naked yet not ashamed, such cool, judicious, scientific atrocity, seemed rather to belong
to a fiend than to the most depraved of men. Principles which the most hardened ruffian
would scarcely hint to his most trusted accomplice, or avow, without the disguise of some
palliating sophism, even to his own mind, are professed without the slightest
circumlocution, and assumed as the fundamental axioms of all political science.
It is not strange that ordinary readers should regard the author of such a book as the
most depraved and shameless of human beings. Wise men, however, have always been inclined
to look with great suspicion on the angels and demons of the multitude; and, in the
present instance, several circumstances have led even superficial observers to question
the justice of the vulgar decision. It is notorious that Machiavelli was, through life, a
zealous republican. In the same year in which he composed his manual of
"Kingcraft," he suffered imprisonment and torture in the cause of public
liberty. It seems inconceivable that the martyr of freedom should have designedly acted as
the apostle of tyranny. Several eminent writers have, therefore, endeavored to detect in
this unfortunate performance some concealed meaning, more consistent with the character
and conduct of the author than that which appears at the first glance.
One hypothesis is, that Machiavelli intended to practice on the young Lorenzo de'
Medici a fraud similar to that which Sunderland is said to have employed against our James
II, and that he urged his pupil to violent and perfidious measures, as the surest means of
accelerating the moment of deliverance and revenge. Another supposition, which Lord Bacon
seems to countenance, is that the treatise was merely a piece of grave irony, intended to
warn nations against the arts of ambitious men. It would be easy to show that neither of
these solutions is consistent with many passages in "The Prince" itself. But the
most decisive refutation is that which is furnished by the other works of Machiavelli. In
all the writings which he gave to the public, and in all those which the research of
editors has, in the course of three centuries, discovered; in his comedies, designed for
the entertainment of the multitude; in his "Comments on Livy," intended for the
perusal of the most enthusiastic patriots of Florence; in his history, inscribed to one of
the most amiable and estimable of the popes; in his public despatches; in his private
memoranda - the same obliquity of moral principle for which "The Prince" is so
severely censured is more or less discernible. We doubt whether it would be possible to
find, in all the many volumes of his compositions, a single expression indicating that
dissimulation and treachery had ever struck him as discreditable.
After this, it may seem ridiculous to say that we are acquainted with few writings
which exhibit so much elevation of sentiment, so pure and warm a zeal for the public good,
or so just a view of the duties and rights of citizens, as those of Machiavelli. Yet so it
is. And even from "The Prince" itself we could select many passages in support
of this remark. To a reader of our age and country, this inconsistency is, at first,
perfectly bewildering. The whole man seems to be an enigma, a grotesque assemblage of
incongruous qualities, selfishness and generosity, cruelty and benevolence, craft and
simplicity, abject villany and romantic heroism. One sentence is such as a veteran
diplomatist would scarcely write in cipher for the direction of his most confidential spy:
the next seems to be extracted from a theme composed by an ardent school-boy on the death
of Leonidas. An act of dexterous perfidy and an act of patriotic self-devotion call forth
the same kind and the same degree of respectful admiration. The moral sensibility of the
writer seems at once to be morbidly obtuse and morbidly acute. Two characters altogether
dissimilar are united in him. They are not merely joined, but interwoven. They are the
warp and the woof of his mind; and their combination, like that of the variegated threads
in shot silk, gives to the whole texture a glancing and ever-changing appearance. The
explanation might have been easy if he had been a very weak or a very affected man. But he
was evidently neither the one nor the other. His works prove, beyond all contradiction,
that his understanding was strong, his taste pure, and his sense of the ridiculous
exquisitely keen.
This is strange, and yet the strangest is behind. There is no reason whatever to think
that those amongst whom he lived saw anything shocking or incongruous in his writings.
Abundant proofs remain of the high estimation in which both his works and his person were
held by the most respectable among his contemporaries. Clement VII patronized the
publication of those very books which the Council of Trent, in the following generation,
pronounced unfit for the perusal of Christians. Some members of the democratical party
censured the secretary for dedicating "The Prince" to a patron who bore the
unpopular name of Medici. But, to those immoral doctrines which have since called forth
such severe reprehensions no exception appears to have been taken. The cry against them
was first raised beyond the Alps, and seems to have been heard with amazement in Italy.
The earliest assailant, as far as we are aware, was a countryman of our own, Cardinal
Pole. The author of the "Anti-Machiavelli" was a French Protestant.
It is, therefore, in the state of moral feeling among the Italians of those times that
we must seek for the real explanation of what seems most mysterious in the life and
writings of this remarkable man. As this is a subject which suggests many interesting
considerations, both political and metaphysical, we shall make no apology for discussing
it at some length.
During the gloomy and disastrous centuries which followed the downfall of the Roman
Empire, Italy had preserved, in a far greater degree than any other part of western
Europe, the traces of ancient civilization. The night which descended upon her was the
night of an Arctic summer. The dawn began to reappear before the last reflection of the
preceding sunset had faded from the horizon. It was in the time of the French Merovingians
and of the Saxon Heptarchy that ignorance and ferocity seemed to have done their worst.
Yet even then the Neapolitan provinces, recognizing the authority of the Eastern Empire,
preserved something of Eastern knowledge and refinement. Rome, protected by the sacred
character of her pontiffs, enjoyed at least comparative security and repose. Even in those
regions where the sanguinary Lombards had fixed their monarchy, there was incomparably
more of wealth, of information, of physical comfort, and of social order, than could be
found in Gaul, Britain, or Germany.
That which most distinguished Italy from the neighboring countries was the importance
which the population of the towns, at a very early period, began to acquire. Some cities
had been founded in wild and remote situations, by fugitives who had escaped from the rage
of the barbarians. Such were Venice and Genoa, which preserved their freedom by their
obscurity, till they became able to preserve it by their power. Other cities seem to have
retained, under all the changing dynasties of invaders, under Odoacer and Theodoric,
Narses and Alboin, the municipal institutions which had been conferred on them by the
liberal policy of the Great Republic. In provinces which the central government was too
feeble either to protect or to oppress, these institutions gradually acquired stability
and vigor. The citizens, defended by their walls, and governed by their own magistrates
and their own by-laws, enjoyed a considerable share of republican independence. Thus a
strong democratic spirit was called into action. The Carlovingian sovereigns were too
imbecile to subdue it. The generous policy of Otho encouraged it. It might perhaps have
been suppressed by a close coalition between the Church and the empire. It was fostered
and invigorated by their disputes. In the twelfth century it attained its full vigor, and,
after a long and doubtful conflict, triumphed over the abilities and courage of the
Swabian princes.
The assistance of the ecclesiastical power had greatly contributed to the success of
the Guelfs. That success would, however, have been a doubtful good, if its only effect had
been to substitute a moral for a political servitude, and to exalt the popes at the
expense of the Caesars. Happily the public mind of Italy had long contained the seeds of
free opinions, which were now rapidly developed by the genial influence of free
institutions. The people of that country had observed the whole machinery of the Church,
its saints and its miracles, its lofty pretensions, and its splendid ceremonial, its
worthless blessings and its harmless curses, too long and too closely to be duped. They
stood behind the scenes on which others were gazing with childish awe and interest. They
witnessed the arrangement of the pulleys, and the manufacture of the thunders. They saw
the natural faces, and heard the natural voices, of the actors. Distant nations looked on
the Pope as the vicegerent of the Almighty, the oracle of the All-Wise, the umpire from
whose decisions, in the disputes either of theologians or of kings, no Christian ought to
appeal. The Italians were acquainted with all the follies of his youth, and with all the
dishonest arts by which he had attained power. They knew how often he had employed the
keys of the Church to release himself from the most sacred engagements, and its wealth to
pamper his mistresses and nephews. The doctrines and rites of the established religion
they treated with decent reverence. But, though they still called themselves Catholics,
they had ceased to be papists. Those spiritual arms which carried terror into the palaces
and camps of the proudest sovereigns excited only contempt in the immediate neighborhood
of the Vatican. Alexander, when he commanded our Henry II to submit to the lash before the
tomb of a rebellious subject, was himself an exile. The Romans, apprehending that he
entertained designs against their liberties, had driven him from their city; and, though
he solemnly promised to confine himself for the future to his spiritual functions, they
still refused to readmit him.
In every other part of Europe, a large and powerful privileged class trampled on the
people, and defied the government. But, in the most flourishing parts of Italy, the feudal
nobles were reduced to comparative insignificance. In some districts they took shelter
under the protection of the powerful commonwealths which they were unable to oppose, and
gradually sank into the mass of burghers. In other places, they possessed great influence;
but it was an influence widely different from that which was exercised by the aristocracy
of any trans-Alpine kingdom. They were not petty princes, but eminent citizens. Instead of
strengthening their fastnesses among the mountains, they embellished their palaces in the
market-place. The state of society in the Neapolitan dominions, and in some parts of the
ecclesiastical State, more nearly resembled that which existed in the great monarchies of
Europe. But the governments of Lombardy and Tuscany, through all their revolutions,
preserved a different character. A people, when assembled in a town, is far more
formidable to its rulers than when dispersed over a wide extent of country. The most
arbitrary of the Caesars found it necessary to feed and divert the inhabitants of their
unwieldy capital at the expense of the provinces. The citizens of Madrid have more than
once besieged their sovereign in his own palace, and extorted from him the most
humiliating concessions. The sultans have often been compelled to propitiate the furious
rabble of Constantinople with the head of an unpopular vizier. From the same cause, there
was a certain tinge of democracy in the monarchies and aristocracies of northern Italy.
Thus liberty, partially indeed and transiently, revisited Italy; and with liberty came
commerce and empire, science and taste, all the comforts and all the ornaments of life.
The Crusades, from which the inhabitants of other countries gained nothing but relics and
wounds, brought to the rising commonwealths of the Adriatic and Tyrrhene seas a large
increase of wealth, dominion, and knowledge. The moral and the geographical position of
those commonwealths enabled them to profit alike by the barbarism of the West and by the
civilization of the East. Italian ships covered every sea. Italian factories rose on every
shore. The tables of Italian money-changers were set in every city. Manufactures
flourished. Banks were established. The operations of the commercial machine were
facilitated by many useful and beautiful inventions. We doubt whether any country of
Europe, our own excepted, has at the present time reached so high a point of wealth and
civilization as some parts of Italy had attained 400 years ago. Historians rarely descend
to those details from which alone the real estate of a community can be collected. Hence
posterity is too often deceived by the vague hyperboles of poets and rhetoricians, who
mistake the splendor of a court for the happiness of a people. Fortunately, John Villani
has given us an example and precise account of the state of Florence in the early part of
the fourteenth century. The revenue of the republic amounted to 300,000 florins, a sum
which, allowing for the depreciation of the precious metals, was at least equivalent to
pounds 600,000 sterling - a larger sum than England and Ireland, two centuries ago,
yielded annually to Elizabeth. The manufacture of wool alone employed 200 factories and
30,000 workmen. The cloth annually produced sold, at an average, for 1,200,000 florins - a
sum fully equal, in exchangeable value, to pounds 2,500,000 of our money. Four hundred
thousand florins were annually coined. Eighty banks conducted the commercial operations,
not of Florence only, but of all Europe. The transactions of these establishments were
sometimes of a magnitude which may surprise even the contemporaries of the Barings and the
Rothschilds. Two houses advanced to Edward III of England upwards of 300,000 marks, at a
time when the mark contained more silver than fifty shillings of the present day, and when
the value of silver was more than quadruple of what it now is. The city, and its environs
contained 170,000 inhabitants. In the various schools about 10,000 children were taught to
read, 1,200 studied arithmetic, 600 received a learned education.
The progress of elegant literature and of the fine arts was proportioned to that of the
public prosperity. Under the despotic successors of Augustus all the fields of the
intellect had been turned into arid wastes, still marked out by formal boundaries, still
retaining the traces of old cultivation, but yielding neither flowers nor fruit. The
deluge of barbarism came. It swept away all the landmarks. It obliterated all the signs of
former tillage. But, it fertilized while it devastated. When it receded, the wilderness
was as the garden of God, rejoicing on every side, laughing, clapping its hands, pouring
forth, in spontaneous abundance, everything brilliant or fragrant or nourishing. A new
language, characterized by simple sweetness and simple energy, had attained perfection. No
tongue ever furnished more gorgeous and vivid tints to poetry; nor was it long before a
poet appeared who knew how to employ them. Early in the fourteenth century came forth
"The Divine Comedy," beyond comparison the greatest work of imagination which
had appeared since the poems of Homer. The following generation produced indeed no second
Dante, but it was eminently distinguished by general intellectual activity. The study of
the Latin writers had never been wholly neglected in Italy. But Petrarch introduced a more
profound, liberal, and elegant scholarship, had communicated to his countrymen that
enthusiasm for the literature, the history, and the antiquities of Rome, which divided his
own heart with a frigid mistress and a more frigid muse. Boccaccio turned their attention
to the more sublime and graceful models of Greece.
From this time, the admiration of learning and genius became almost an idolatry among
the people of Italy. Kings and republics, cardinals and doges, vied with each other in
honoring and flattering Petrarch. Embassies from rival States solicited the honor of his
instructions. His coronation agitated the Court of Naples and the people of Rome as much
as the most important political transaction could have done. To collect books and
antiques, to found professorships, to patronize men of learning, became almost universal
fashions among the great. The spirit of literary research allied itself to that of
commercial enterprise. Every place to which the merchant princes of Florence extended
their gigantic traffic, from the bazars of the Tigris to the monasteries of the Clyde, was
ransacked for medals and manuscripts. Architecture, painting, and sculpture were
munificently encouraged. Indeed, it would be difficult to name an Italian of eminence,
during the period of which we speak, who, whatever may have been his general character,
did not at least affect a love of letters and of the arts.
Knowledge and public prosperity continued to advance together. Both attained their
meridian in the age of Lorenzo the Magnificent. We cannot refrain from quoting the
splendid passage in which the Tuscan Thucydides describes the state of Italy at that
period. "Ridotta tutta in somma pace e tranquillita coltivata non meno ne luogti piu
montusoi e piu sterili che nelle pianure e regioni piu fertili, ne sottoposta ad altro
imperio che de suoi medesimi, non solo era abbondantissima d' abitatori e di ricchezze; ma
illustrata sommamente dalla magnificenza di molti principi, dallo splendore di molte
nobilissime e bellissime citta, dalla sedia e maesta della religione, fioriva d' uomini
prestantissimi nell' amministrazione delle cose pubbliche, e d' ingegni molto nobili in
tutte le scienze, ed in qualunque arte preclara ed industriosa."2 When we
peruse this just and splendid description, we can scarcely persuade ourselves that we are
reading of times in which the annals of England and France present us only with a
frightful spectacle of poverty, barbarity, and ignorance. From the oppressions of
illiterate masters, and the sufferings of a degraded peasantry, it is delightful to turn
to the opulent and enlightened States of Italy, to the vast and magnificent cities, the
ports, the arsenals, the villas, the museums, the libraries, the marts filled with every
article of comfort or luxury, the factories swarming with artisans, the Apennines covered
with rich cultivation up to their very summits, the Po wafting the harvests of Lombardy to
the granaries of Venice, and carrying back the silks of Bengal and the furs of Siberia to
the palaces of Milan. With peculiar pleasure every cultivated mind must repose on the
fair, the happy, the glorious Florence, the halls which rang with the mirth of Pulci, the
cell where twinkled the midnight lamp of Politian, the statues on which the young eye of
Michael Angelo glared with the frenzy of a kindred inspiration, the gardens in which
Lorenzo meditated some sparkling song for the May-day dance of the Etrurian virgins. Alas
for the beautiful city! Alas for the wit and the learning, the genius and the love!
[Footnote 2: "Enjoying the utmost peace and tranquillity, cultivated as well in
the most mountainous and barren places as in the plains and most fertile regions, and not
subject to any other dominion than that of its own people, it not only overflowed with
inhabitants and with riches, but was highly adorned by the magnificence of many princes,
by the splendor of many renowned and beautiful cities, by the abode and majesty of
religion, and abounded in men who excelled in the administration of public affairs and in
minds most eminent in all the sciences and in every noble and useful art." -
Guicciardini, "History of Italy," Book I., trans. Montague.]
"Le donne, e i cavalieri, gli affanni e gli agi, Che ne'nvogliava amore e cortesia
La dove i cuor son fatti si malvagi."3
[Footnote 3: "The ladies and the knights, the toils and sports to which love and
courtesy stirred our desire there where all hearts have grown so evil." Dante,
"Purgatorio," Canto 14, ll. 109-111.]
A time was at hand when all the seven vials of the Apocalypse were to be poured forth
and shaken out over those pleasant countries - a time of slaughter, famine, beggary,
infamy, slavery, despair.
Part II
In the Italian States, as in many natural bodies, untimely decrepitude was the penalty
of precocious maturity. Their early greatness, and their early decline, are principally to
be attributed to the same cause - the preponderance which the towns acquired in the
political system.
In a community of hunters or of shepherds every man easily and necessarily becomes a
soldier. His ordinary avocations are perfectly compatible with all the duties of military
service. However remote may be the expedition on which he is bound, he finds it easy to
transport with him the stock from which he derives his subsistence. The whole people in an
army, the whole year a march. Such was the state of society which facilitated the gigantic
conquests of Attila and Tamerlane.
But a people which subsists by the cultivation of the earth is in a very different
situation. The husbandman is bound to the soil on which he labors. A long campaign would
be ruinous to him. Still his pursuits are such as to give his frame both the active and
the passive strength necessary to a soldier. Nor do they, at least in the infancy of
agricultural science, demand his uninterrupted attention. At particular times of the year
he is almost wholly unemployed, and can, without injury to himself, afford the time
necessary for a short expedition. Thus the legions of Rome were supplied during its
earlier wars. The season during which the fields did not require the presence of the
cultivators sufficed for a short inroad and a battle. These operations, too frequently
interrupted to produce decisive results, yet served to keep up among the people a degree
of discipline and courage which rendered them not only secure but formidable. The archers
and billmen of the Middle Ages, who, with provisions for forty days at their back, left
the fields for the camp, were troops of the same description.
But when commerce and manufactures begin to flourish, a great change takes place. The
sedentary habits of the desk and the loom render the exertions and hardships of war
insupportable. The business of traders and artisans requires their constant presence and
attention. In such a community there is little superfluous time; but there is generally
much superfluous money. Some members of the society are, therefore, hired to relieve the
rest from a task inconsistent with their habits and engagements.
The history of Greece is, in this, as in many other respects, the best commentary on
the history of Italy. Five hundred years before the Christian era the citizens of the
republics round the Aegean Sea formed perhaps the finest militia that ever existed. As
wealth and refinement advanced, the system underwent a gradual alteration. The Ionian
States were the first in which commerce and the arts were cultivated, and the first in
which the ancient discipline decayed. Within eighty years after the battle of Plataea,
mercenary troops were everywhere plying for battles and sieges. In the time of
Demosthenes, it was scarcely possible to persuade or compel the Athenians to enlist for
foreign service. The laws of Lycurgus prohibited trade and manufactures. The Spartans,
therefore, continued to form a national force long after their neighbors had begun to hire
soldiers. But their military spirit declined with their singular institutions. In the
second century before Christ, Greece contained only one nation of warriors, the savage
highlanders of Aetolia, who were some generations behind their countrymen in civilization
and intelligence.
All the causes which produced these effects among the Greeks acted still more strongly
on the modern Italians. Instead of a power like Sparta, in its nature warlike, they had
amongst them an ecclesiastical state, in its nature pacific. Where there are numerous
slaves, every freeman is induced by the strongest motives to familiarize himself with the
use of arms. The commonwealths of Italy did not, like those of Greece, swarm with
thousands of these household enemies. Lastly, the mode in which military operations were
conducted during the prosperous times of Italy was peculiarly unfavorable to the formation
of an efficient militia. Men covered with iron from head to foot, armed with ponderous
lances, and mounted on horses of the largest breed, were considered as composing the
strength of an army. The infantry was regarded as comparatively worthless, and was
neglected till it became really so. These tactics maintained their ground for centuries in
most parts of Europe. That foot-soldiers could withstand the charge of heavy cavalry was
thought utterly impossible, till, towards the close of the fifteenth century, the rude
mountaineers of Switzerland dissolved the spell, and astounded the most experienced
generals by receiving the dreaded shock on an impenetrable forest of pikes.
The use of the Grecian spear, the Roman sword, or the modern bayonet, might be acquired
with comparative ease. But nothing short of the daily exercise of years could train the
man at arms to support his ponderous panoply, and manage his unwieldy weapon. Throughout
Europe this most important branch of war became a separate profession. Beyond the Alps,
indeed, though a profession, it was not generally a trade. It was the duty and the
amusement of a large class of country gentlemen. It was the service by which they held
their lands, and the diversion by which, in the absence of mental resources, they beguiled
their leisure. But in the northern States of Italy, as we have already remarked, the
growing power of the cities, where it had not exterminated this order of men, had
completely changed their habits. Here, therefore, the practice of employing mercenaries
became universal, at a time when it was almost unknown in other countries.
When war becomes the trade of a separate class the least dangerous course left to a
government is to form that class into a standing army. It is scarcely possible that men
can pass their lives in the service of one State, without feeling some interest in its
greatness. Its victories are their victories. Its defeats are their defeats. The contract
loses something of its mercantile character. The services of the soldier are considered as
the effects of patriotic zeal, his pay as the tribute of national gratitude. To betray the
power which employs him, to be even remiss in its service, are in his eyes the most
atrocious and degrading of crimes.
When the princes and commonwealths of Italy began to use hired troops, their wisest
course would have been to form separate military establishments. Unhappily this was not
done. The mercenary warriors of the Peninsula, instead of being attached to the service of
different powers, were regarded as the common property of all. The connection between the
State and its defenders was reduced to the most simple and naked traffic. The adventurer
brought his horse, his weapons, his strength, and his experience, into the market. Whether
the King of Naples or the Duke of Milan, the Pope or the Signory of Florence, struck the
bargain, was to him a matter of perfect indifference. He was for the highest wages and the
longest term. When the campaign for which he had contracted was finished, there was
neither law nor punctilio to prevent him from instantly turning his arms against his late
masters. The soldier was altogether disjoined from the citizen and from the subject.
The natural consequences followed. Left to the conduct of men who neither loved those
whom they defended, nor hated those whom they opposed, who were often bound by stronger
ties to the army against which they fought than to the State which they served, who lost
by the termination of the conflict, and gained by its prolongation, war completely changed
its character. Every man came into the field of battle impressed with the knowledge, that,
in a few days, he might be taking the pay of the power against which he was then employed,
and fighting by the side of his enemies against his associates. The strongest interests
and the strongest feelings concurred to mitigate the hostility of those who had lately
been brethren in arms, and who might soon be brethren in arms once more. Their common
profession was a bond of union not to be forgotten, even when they were engaged in the
service of contending parties. Hence it was that operations, languid and indecisive beyond
any recorded in history, marches and countermarches, pillaging expeditions and blockades,
bloodless capitulations and equally bloodless combats, make up the military history of
Italy during the course of nearly two centuries. Might armies fight from sunrise to
sunset. A great victory is won. Thousands of prisoners are taken, and hardly a life is
lost. A pitched battle seems to have been really less dangerous than an ordinary civil
tumult.
Courage was now no longer necessary, even to the military character. Men grew old in
camps, and acquired the highest renown by their warlike achievements, without being once
required to face serious danger. The political consequences are too well known. The
richest and most enlightened part of the world was left undefended to the assaults of
every barbarous invader, to the brutality of Switzerland, the insolence of France, and the
fierce rapacity of Aragon. The moral effects which followed from this state of things were
still more remarkable.
Amongst the rude nations which lay beyond the Alps, valor was absolutely indispensable.
Without it none could be eminent, few could be secure. Cowardice was, therefore, naturally
considered as the foulest reproach. Among the polished Italians, enriched by commerce,
governed by law, and passionately attached to literature, everything was done by
superiority of intelligence. Their very wars, more pacific than the peace of their
neighbors, required rather civil than military qualifications. Hence, while courage was
the point of honor in other countries, ingenuity became the point of honor in Italy.
From these principles were deduced, by processes strictly analogous, two opposite
systems of fashionable morality. Through the greater part of Europe, the vices which
peculiarly belong to timid dispositions, and which are the natural defence of weakness,
fraud, and hypocrisy, have always been most disreputable. On the other hand, the excesses
of haughty and daring spirits have been treated with indulgence, and even with respect.
The Italians regarded with corresponding lenity those crimes which require self-command,
address, quick observation, fertile invention, and profound knowledge of human nature.
Such a prince as our Henry V would have been the idol of the North. The follies of his
youth, the selfish ambition of his manhood, the Lollards roasted at slow fires, the
prisoners massacred on the field of battle, the expiring lease of priestcraft renewed for
another century, the dreadful legacy of a causeless and hopeless war bequeathed to a
people who had no interest in its event - everything is forgotten but the victory of
Agincourt. Francis Sforza, on the other hand, was the model of Italian heroes. He made his
employers and his rivals alike his tools. He first overpowered his open enemies by the
help of faithless allies: he then armed himself against his allies with the spoils taken
from his enemies. By his incomparable dexterity, he raised himself from the precarious and
dependent situation of a military adventurer to the first throne of Italy. To such a man
much was forgiven hollow friendship, ungenerous enmity, violated faith. Such are the
opposite errors which men commit, when their morality is not a science, but a taste, when
they abandon eternal principles for accidental associations.
We have illustrated our meaning by an instance taken from history. We will select
another from fiction. Othello murders his wife; he gives orders for the murder of his
lieutenant; he ends by murdering himself. Yet he never loses the esteem and affection of
Northern readers. His intrepid and ardent spirit redeems everything. The unsuspecting
confidence with which he listens to his adviser, the agony with which he shrinks from the
thought of shame, the tempest of passion with which he commits his crimes, and the haughty
fearlessness with which he avows them, give an extraordinary interest to his character.
Iago, on the contrary, is the object of universal loathing. Many are inclined to suspect
that Shakespeare has been seduced into an exaggeration unusual with him, and has drawn a
monster who has no archetype in human nature. Now, we suspect that an Italian audience in
the fifteenth century would have felt very differently. Othello would have inspired
nothing but detestation and contempt. The folly with which he trusts the friendly
professions of a man whose promotion he had obstructed, the credulity with which he takes
unsupported assertions, and trivial circumstances, for unanswerable proofs, the violence
with which he silences the exculpation till the exculpation can only aggravate his misery,
would have excited the abhorrence and disgust of his spectators. The conduct of Iago they
would assuredly have condemned, but they would have condemned it as we condemn that of his
victim. Something of interest and respect would have mingled with their disapprobation.
The readiness of the traitor's wit, the clearness of his judgment, the skill with which he
penetrates the dispositions of others, and conceals his own, would have insured to him a
certain portion of their esteem.
So wide was the difference between the Italians and their neighbors. A similar
difference existed between the Greeks of the second century before Christ, and their
masters, the Romans. The conquerors, brave and resolute, faithful to their engagements,
and strongly influenced by religious feelings, were, at the same time, ignorant,
arbitrary, and cruel. With the vanquished people were deposited all the art, the science,
and the literature of the Western world. In poetry, in philosophy, in painting, in
architecture, in sculpture, they had no rivals. Their manners were polished, their
perceptions acute, their invention ready; they were tolerant, affable, humane; but of
courage and sincerity they were almost utterly destitute. Every rude centurion consoled
himself for his intellectual inferiority, by remarking that knowledge and taste seemed
only to make men atheists, cowards and slaves. The distinction long continued to be
strongly marked, and furnished and admirable subject for the fierce sarcasms of Juvenal.
The citizen of an Italian commonwealth was the Greek of the time of Juvenal and the
Greek of the time of Pericles, joined in one. Like the former, he was timid and pliable,
artful and mean. But, like the latter, he had a country. Its independence and prosperity
were dear to him. If his character were degraded by some base crimes, it was, on the other
hand, ennobled by public spirit and by an honorable ambition.
A vice sanctioned by the general opinion is merely a vice. The evil terminates in
itself. A vice condemned by the general opinion produces a pernicious effect on the whole
character. The former is a local malady, the latter a constitutional taint. When the
reputation of the offender is lost, he, too, often flings the remains of his virtue after
it in despair. The Highland gentleman, who, a century ago, lived by taking blackmail from
his neighbors, committed the same crime for which Wild was accompanied to Tyburn by the
huzzas of 200,000 people. But there can be no doubt that he was a much less depraved man
than Wild. The deed for which Mrs. Brownrigg was hanged, sinks into nothing when compared
with the conduct of the Roman who treated the public to one hundred pairs of gladiators.
Yet we should greatly wrong such a Roman if we supposed that his disposition was as cruel
as that of Mrs. Brownrigg. In our own country, a woman forfeits her place in society by
what, in a man, is too commonly considered as an honorable distinction, and at worst as a
venial error. The consequence is notorious. The moral principle of a woman is frequently
more impaired by a single lapse from virtue than that of a man by twenty years of
intrigues. Classical antiquity would furnish us with instances stronger, if possible, than
those to which we have referred.
We must apply this principle to the case before us. Habits of dissimulation and
falsehood, no doubt, mark a man of our age and country as utterly worthless and abandoned.
But it by no means follows that a similar judgment would be just in the case of an Italian
in the Middle Ages. On the contrary, we frequently find those faults which we are
accustomed to consider as certain indications of a mind altogether depraved, in company
with great and good qualities, with generosity, with benevolence, with disinterestedness.
From such a state of society, Palamedes, in the admirable dialogue of Hume, might have
drawn illustrations of his theory as striking as any of those with which Fourli furnished
him. These are not, we well know, the lessons which historians are generally most careful
to teach, or readers most willing to learn. But they are not therefore useless. How Philip
disposed his troops at Chaeronea, where Hannibal crossed the Alps, whether Mary blew up
Darnley, or Siquier shot Charles XII, and the thousand other questions of the same
description, are in themselves unimportant. The inquiry may amuse us, but the decision
leaves us no wiser. He alone reads history aright, who, observing how powerfully
circumstances influence the feelings and opinions of men, how often vices pass into
virtues, and paradoxes into axioms, learns to distinguish what is accidental and
transitory in human nature, from what is essential and immutable.
In this respect, no history suggests more important reflections than that of the Tuscan
and Lombard commonwealths. The character of the Italian statesman seems, at first sight, a
collection of contradictions, a phantom as monstrous as the portress of hell in Milton,
half divinity, half snake, majestic and beautiful above, grovelling and poisonous below.
We see a man whose thoughts and words have no connection with each other, who never
hesitates at an oath when he wishes to seduce, who never wants a pretext when he is
inclined to betray. His cruelties spring, not from the heat of blood, or the insanity of
uncontrolled power, but from deep and cool meditation. His passions, like well-trained
troops, are impetuous by rule, and in their most headstrong fury never forget the
discipline to which they have been accustomed. His whole soul is occupied with vast and
complicated schemes of ambition, yet his aspect and language exhibit nothing but
philosophical moderation. Hatred and revenge eat into his heart; yet every look is a
cordial smile, every gesture a familiar caress. He never excites the suspicion of his
adversaries by petty provocations. His purpose is disclosed, only when it is accomplished.
His face is unruffled, his speech is courteous, till vigilance is laid asleep, till a
vital point is exposed, till a sure aim is taken; and then he strikes for the first and
last time. Military courage, the boast of the sottish German, of the frivolous and prating
Frenchman, of the romantic and arrogant Spaniard, he neither possesses nor values. He
shuns danger, not because he is insensible to shame, but because, in the society in which
he lives, timidity has ceased to be shameful. To do an injury openly is, in his
estimation, as wicked as to do it secretly, and far less profitable. With him the most
honorable means are those which are the surest, the speediest, and the darkest. He cannot
comprehend how a man should scruple to deceive those whom he does not scruple to destroy.
He would think it madness to declare open hostilities against rivals whom he might stab in
a friendly embrace, or poison in a consecrated wafer.
Yet this man, black with the vices which we consider as most loathsome, traitor,
hypocrite, coward, assassin, was by no means destitute even of those virtues which we
generally consider as indicating superior elevation of character. In civil courage, in
perseverance, in presence of mind, those barbarous warriors, who were foremost in the
battle or the breach, were far his inferiors. Even the dangers which he avoided with a
caution almost pusillanimous never confused his perceptions, never paralyzed his inventive
faculties, never wrung out one secret from his smooth tongue and his inscrutable brow.
Though a dangerous enemy, and a still more dangerous accomplice, he could be a just and
beneficent ruler. With so much unfairness in his policy, there was an extraordinary degree
of fairness in his intellect. Indifferent to truth in the transactions of life, he was
honestly devoted to truth in the researches of speculation. Wanton cruelty was not in his
nature. On the contrary, where no political object was at stake, his disposition was soft
and humane. The susceptibility of his nerves and the activity of his imagination inclined
him to sympathize with the feelings of others, and to delight in the charities and
courtesies of social life. Perpetually descending to actions which might seem to mark a
mind diseased through all its faculties, he had nevertheless an exquisite sensibility,
both for the natural and the moral sublime, for every graceful and every lofty conception.
Habits of petty intrigue and dissimulation might have rendered him incapable of great
general views, but that the expanding effect of his philosophical studies counteracted the
narrowing tendency. He had the keenest enjoyment of wit, eloquence, and poetry. The fine
arts profited alike by the severity of his judgment, and by the liberality of his
patronage. The portraits of some of the remarkable Italians of those times are perfectly
in harmony with this description. Ample and majestic foreheads; brows strong and dark, but
not frowning; eyes of which the calm, full gaze, while it expresses nothing, seems to
discern everything; cheeks pale with thought and sedentary habits; lips formed with
feminine delicacy, but compressed with more than masculine decision-mark out men at once
enterprising and timid, men equally skilled in detecting the purposes of others, in and
concealing their own, men who must have been formidable enemies and unsafe allies, but
men, at the same time, whose tempers were mild and equable, and who possessed an amplitude
and subtlety of intellect which would have rendered them eminent either in active or in
contemplative life, and fitted them either to govern or to instruct mankind.
Every age and every nation has certain characteristic vices, which prevail almost
universally, which scarcely any person scruples to avow, and which even rigid moralists
but faintly censure. Succeeding generations change the fashion of their morals, with the
fashion of their hats and their coaches; take some other kind of wickedness under their
patronage, and wonder at the depravity of their ancestors. Nor is this all. Posterity,
that high court of appeal which is never tired of eulogizing its own justice and
discernment, acts on such occasions like a Roman dictator after a general mutiny. Finding
the delinquents too numerous to be all punished, it selects some of them at hazard, to
bear the whole penalty of an offence in which they are not more deeply implicated than
those who escape. Whether decimation be a convenient mode of military execution, we know
not; but we solemnly protest against the introduction of such a principle into the
philosophy of history.
In the present instance, the lot has fallen on Machiavelli, a man whose public conduct
was upright and honorable, whose views of morality, where they differed from those of the
persons around him, seemed to have differed for the better, and whose only fault was,
that, having adopted some of the maxims then generally received, he arranged them more
luminously, and expressed them more forcibly, than any other writer.
Having now, we hope, in some degree cleared the personal character of Machiavelli, we
come to the consideration of his works. As a poet, he is not entitled to a very high
place;4 but the comedies deserve more attention.
[Footnote 4: In the original essay Macaulay had here some critical remarks on the
poetry of Machiavelli, but he omitted them on republication.]
The "Mandragola," in particular, is superior to the best of Goldoni, and
inferior only to the best of Moliere. It is the work of a man who, if he had devoted
himself to the drama, would probably have attained the highest eminence, and produced a
permanent and salutary effect on the national taste. This we infer, not so much from the
degree as from the kind of its excellence. There are compositions which indicate still
greater talent, and which are perused with still greater delight, from which we should
have drawn very different conclusions. Books quite worthless are quite harmless. The sure
sign of the general decline of an art is the frequent occurrence, not of deformity, but of
misplaced beauty. In general, tragedy is corrupted by eloquence, and comedy by wit.
The real object of the drama is the exhibition of human character. This, we conceive,
is no arbitrary canon, originating in local and temporary associations, like those canons
which regulate the number of acts in a play, or of syllables in a line. To this
fundamental law every other regulation is subordinate. The situations which most signally
develop character form the best plot. The mother tongue of the passions is the best style.
This principle, rightly understood, does not debar the poet from any grace of
composition. There is no style in which some man may not, under some circumstances,
express himself. There is, therefore, no style which the drama rejects, none which it does
not occasionally require. It is in the discernment of place, of time, and of person, that
the inferior artists fail. The fantastic rhapsody of Mercutio, the elaborate declamation
of Antony, are, where Shakespeare has placed them, natural and pleasing. But Dryden would
have made Mercutio challenge Tybalt in hyperboles as fanciful as those in which he
describes the chariot of Mab. Corneille would have represented Antony as scolding and
coaxing Cleopatra with all the measured rhetoric of a funeral oration.
No writers have injured the comedy of England so deeply as Congreve and Sheridan. Both
were men of splendid wit and polished taste. Unhappily, they made all their characters in
their own likeness. Their works bear the same relation to the legitimate drama which a
transparency bears to a painting. There are no delicate touches, no hues imperceptibly
fading into each other: the whole is lighted up with a universal glare. Outlines and tints
are forgotten in the common blaze which illuminates all. The flowers and fruits of the
intellect abound; but it is the abundance of a jungle, not of a garden, unwholesome,
bewildering, unprofitable from its very plenty, rank from its very fragrance. Every fop,
every boor, every valet, is a man of wit. The very butts and dupes, Tattle, Witwould,
Puff, Acres, outshine the whole Hotel of Rambouillet. To prove the whole system of this
school erroneous, it is only necessary to apply the test which dissolved the enchanted
Florimel, to place the true by the false Thalia, to contrast the most celebrated
characters which have been drawn by the writers of whom we speak with the Bastard in
"King John," or the Nurse in "Romeo and Juliet." It was not surely
from want of wit that Shakespeare adopted so different a manner. Benedick and Beatrice
throw Mirabel and Millamant5 into the shade. All the good sayings of the
facetious hours of Absolute and Surface might have been clipped from the single character
of Falstaff without being missed. It would have been easy for that fertile mind to have
given Bardolph and Shallow as much wit as Prince Hal, and to have made Dogberry and Verges
retort on each other in sparkling epigrams. But he knew that such indiscriminate
prodigality was, to use his own admirable language, "from the purpose of playing,
whose end, both at the first and now, was, and is, to hold, as it were, the mirror up to
nature."
[Footnote 5: In Congreve's "Way of the World."]
This digression will enable our readers to understand what we mean when we say, that,
in the "Mandragola," Machiavelli has proved that he completely understood the
nature of the dramatic art, and possessed talents which would have enabled him to excel in
it. By the correct and vigorous delineation of human nature, it produces interest without
a pleasing or skillful plot, and laughter without the least ambition of wit. The lover,
not a very delicate or generous lover, and his adviser the parasite, are drawn with
spirit. The hypocritical confessor is an admirable portrait. He is, if we mistake not, the
original of Father Dominic,6 the best comic character of Dryden. But old Nicias
is the glory of the piece. We cannot call to mind anything that resembles him. The follies
which Moliere ridicules are those of affectation, not those of fatuity. Coxcombs and
pedants, not absolute simpletons, are his game. Shakespeare has indeed a vast assortment
of fools; but the precise species of which we speak is not, if we remember right, to be
found there. Shallow is a fool. But his animal spirits supply, to a certain degree, the
place of cleverness. His talk is to that of Sir John what soda-water is to champagne. It
has the effervescence, though not the body or the flavor. Slender and Sir Andrew Aguecheek
are fools, troubled with an uneasy consciousness of their folly, which, in the latter,
produces meekness and docility, and in the former, awkwardness, obstinacy, and confusion.
Cloten is an arrogant fool, Osric a foppish fool, Ajax a savage fool; but Nicias is, as
Thersites says of Patroclus, a fool positive. His mind is occupied by no strong feeling;
it takes every character, and retains none; its aspect is diversified, not by passions,
but by faint and transitory semblances of passion, a mock joy, a mock fear, a mock love, a
mock pride, which chase each other like shadows over its surface, and vanish as soon as
they appear. He is just idiot enough to be an object, not of pity or horror, but of
ridicule. He bears some resemblance to poor Calandrino, whose mishaps, as recounted by
Boccaccio, have made all Europe merry for more than four centuries. He perhaps resembles
still more closely Simon de Villa, to whom Bruno and Buffalmacco promised the love of the
Countess Civillari. Nicias is, like Simon, of a learned profession; and the dignity with
which he wears the doctoral fur renders his absurdities infinitely more grotesque. The old
Tuscan is the very language for such a being. Its peculiar simplicity gives even to the
most forcible reasoning and the most brilliant wit an infantine air, generally delightful,
but to a foreign reader sometimes a little ludicrous. Heroes and statesmen seem to lisp
when they use it. It becomes Nicias incomparably, and renders all his silliness infinitely
more silly.
[Footnote 6: In Dryden's "Spanish Friar."]
We may add, that the verses with which the "Mandragola" is interspersed
appear to us to be the most spirited and correct of all that Machiavelli has written in
metre. He seems to have entertained the same opinion, for he has introduced some of them
in other places. The contemporaries of the author were not blind to the merits of this
striking piece. It was acted at Florence with the greatest success. Leo X was among its
admirers, and by his order it was represented at Rome.7
[Footnote 7: Nothing can be more evident than that Paulus Jovius designates the
"Mandragola" under the name of the "Nicias." We should not have
noticed what is so perfectly obvious, were it not that this natural and palpable misnomer
has led the sagacious and industrious Bayle into a gross error. - M.]
The "Clizia" is an imitation of the "Casina" of Plautus, which is
itself an imitation of the lost kxnpoumevol of Diphilus.8 Plautus was,
unquestionably, one of the best Latin writers; but the "Casina" is by no means
one of his best plays, nor is it one which offers great facilities to an imitator. The
story is as alien from modern habits of life as the manner in which it is developed from
the modern fashion of composition. The lover remains in the country and the heroine in her
chamber during the whole action, leaving their fate to be decided by a foolish father, a
cunning mother, and two knavish servants. Machiavelli has executed his task with judgment
and taste. He has accommodated the plot to a different state of society, and has very
dexterously connected it with the history of his own times. The relation of the trick put
on the doting old lover is exquisitely humorous. It is far superior to the corresponding
passage in the Latin comedy, and scarcely yields to the account which Falstaff gives of
his ducking.
[Footnote 8: A writer of the Greek "New Comedy," which followed that of
Aristophanes.]
Two other comedies, without titles, the one in prose, the other in verse, appear among
the works of Machiavelli. The former is very short, lively enough, but of no great value.
The latter we can scarcely believe to be genuine. Neither its merits nor its defects
remind us of the reputed author. It was first printed in 1796, from a manuscript
discovered in the celebrated library of the Strozzi. Its genuineness, if we have been
rightly informed, is established solely by the comparison of hands. Our suspicions are
strengthened by the circumstance, that the same manuscript contained a description of the
plague of 1527, which has also, in consequence, been added to the works of Machiavelli. Of
this last composition, the strongest external evidence would scarcely induce us to believe
him guilty. Nothing was ever written more detestable in matter and manner. The narrations,
the reflections, the jokes, the lamentations, are all the very worst of their respective
kinds, at once trite and affected, threadbare tinsel from the Rag Fairs9 and
Monmouth streets9 of literature. A foolish schoolboy might write such a piece,
and, after he had written it, think it much finer than the incomparable introduction of
"The Decameron." But that a shrewd statesman, whose earliest works are
characterized by manliness of thought and language, should, at near sixty years of age,
descend to such puerility, is utterly inconceivable.
[Footnote 9: Old-clothes markets in London.]
The little novel of "Belphegor" is pleasantly conceived, and pleasantly told.
But the extravagance of the satire in some measure injures its effect. Machiavelli was
unhappily married; and his wish to avenge his own cause, and that of his brethren in
misfortune, carried him beyond even the license of fiction. Jonson seems to have combined
some hints taken from this tale, with others from Boccaccio, in the plot of "The
Devil is an Ass," a play which, though not the most highly finished of his
compositions, is perhaps that which exhibits the strongest proofs of genius.
The political correspondence of Machiavelli, first published in 1767, is unquestionably
genuine, and highly valuable. The unhappy circumstances in which his country was placed
during the greater part of his public life gave extraordinary encouragement to diplomatic
talents. From the moment that Charles VIII descended from the Alps the whole character of
Italian politics was changed. The governments of the Peninsula ceased to form an
independent system. Drawn from their old orbit by the attraction of the larger bodies
which now approach them, they became mere satellites of France and Spain. All their
disputes, internal and external, were decided by foreign influence. The contests of
opposite factions were carried on, not as formerly in the Senate house or in the
market-place, but in the ante-chambers of Louis and Ferdinand. Under these circumstances,
the prosperity of the Italian States depended far more on the ability of their foreign
agents, than on the conduct of those who were intrusted with the domestic administration.
The ambassador had to discharge functions far more delicate than transmitting orders of
knighthood, introducing tourists, or presenting his brethren with the homage of his high
consideration. He was an advocate to whose management the dearest interests of his clients
were intrusted, a spy clothed with an inviolable character. Instead of consulting, by a
reserved manner and ambiguous style, the dignity of those whom he represented, he was to
plunge into all the intrigues of the court at which he resided, to discover and flatter
every weakness of the prince, and of the favorite who governed the prince, and of the
lackey who governed the favorite. He was to compliment the mistress, and bribe the
confessor, to panegyrize or supplicate, to laugh or weep, to accommodate himself to every
caprice, to lull every suspicion, to treasure every hint, to be everything, to observe
everything, to endure everything. High as the art of political intrigue had been carried
in Italy, these were times which required it all.
On these arduous errands Machiavelli was frequently employed. He was sent to treat with
the King of the Romans and with the Duke of Valentinois. He was twice ambassador at the
Court of Rome, and thrice at that of France. In these missions, and in several others of
inferior importance, he acquitted himself with great dexterity. His despatches form one of
the most amusing and instructive collections extant. The narratives are clear and
agreeably written, the remarks on men and things clever and judicious. The conversations
are reported in a spirited and characteristic manner. We find ourselves introduced into
the presence of the men who, during twenty eventful years, swayed the destinies of Europe.
Their wit and their folly, their fretfulness and their merriment, are exposed to us. We
are admitted to overhear their chat, and to watch their familiar gestures. It is
interesting and curious to recognize, in circumstances which elude the notice of
historians, the feeble violence and shallow cunning of Louis XII; the bustling
insignificance of Maximilian, cursed with an impotent pruriency for renown, rash yet
timid, obstinate yet fickle, always in a hurry, yet always too late; the fierce and
haughty energy which gave dignity to the eccentricities of Julius; the soft and graceful
manners which masked the insatiable ambition and the implacable hatred of Caesar Borgia.
We have mentioned Caesar Borgia. It is impossible not to pause for a moment on the name
of a man in whom the political morality of Italy was so strongly personified, partially
blended with the sterner lineaments of the Spanish character. On two important occasions
Machiavelli was admitted to his society - once, at the moment when Caesar's splendid
villainy achieved its most signal triumph, when he caught in one snare, and crushed at one
blow, all his most formidable rivals; and again when, exhausted by disease, and
overwhelmed by misfortunes which no human prudence could have averted, he was the prisoner
of the deadliest enemy of his house. These interviews between the greatest speculative and
the greatest practical statesmen of the age are fully described in the
"Correspondence," and form, perhaps, the most interesting part of it. From some
passages in "The Prince," and perhaps also from some indistinct traditions,
several writers have supposed a connection between those remarkable men much closer than
ever existed. The envoy has even been accused of prompting the crimes of the artful and
merciless tyrant. But, from the official documents, it is clear that their intercourse,
though ostensibly amicable, was in reality hostile. It cannot be doubted, however, that
the imagination of Machiavelli was strongly impressed, and his speculations on government
colored, by the observations which he made on the singular character and equally singular
fortunes of a man who, under such disadvantages, had achieved such exploits; who, when
sensuality, varied through innumerable forms, could no longer stimulate his sated mind,
found a more powerful and durable excitement in the intense thirst of empire and revenge;
who emerged from the sloth and luxury of the Roman purple the first prince and general of
the age; who, trained in an unwarlike profession, formed a gallant army out of the dregs
of an unwarlike people; who, after acquiring sovereignty by destroying his enemies,
acquired popularity by destroying his tools; who had begun to employ for the most salutary
ends the power which he had attained by the most atrocious means; who tolerated within the
sphere of his iron despotism no plunderer or oppressor but himself; and who fell at last
amidst the mingled curses and regrets of a people of whom his genius had been the wonder,
and might have been the salvation. Some of those crimes of Borgia which to us appear the
most odious, would not, from causes which we have already considered, have struck an
Italian of the fifteenth century with equal horror. Patriotic feeling also might induce
Machiavelli to look with some indulgence and regret on the memory of the only leader who
could have defended the independence of Italy against the confederate spoilers of Cambray.
Part III
On this subject, Machiavelli felt most strongly. Indeed, the expulsion of the foreign
tyrants, and the restoration of that golden age which had preceded the irruption of
Charles VIII, were projects which, at that time, fascinated all the master-spirits of
Italy. The magnificent vision delighted the great but ill-regulated mind of Julius. It
divided with manuscripts and saucers, painters and falcons, the attention of the frivolous
Leo. It prompted the generous treason of Morone. It imparted a transient energy to the
feeble mind and body of the last Sforza. It excited for one moment an honest ambition in
the false heart of Pescara. Ferocity and insolence were not among the vices of the
national character. To the discriminating cruelties of politicians, committed for great
ends on select victims, the moral code of the Italians was too indulgent. But, though they
might have recourse to barbarity as an expedient, they did not require it as a stimulant.
They turned with loathing from the atrocity of the strangers who seemed to love blood for
its own sake; who, not content with subjugating, were impatient to destroy; who found a
fiendish pleasure in razing magnificent cities, cutting the throats of enemies who cried
for quarter, or suffocating an unarmed population by thousands in the caverns to which it
had fled for safety. Such were the cruelties which daily excited the terror and disgust of
a people among whom, till lately, the worst that a soldier had to fear in a pitched battle
was the loss of his horse and the expense of his ransom. The swinish intemperance of
Switzerland; the wolfish avarice of Spain; the gross licentiousness of the French,
indulged in violation of hospitality, of decency, of love itself; the wanton inhumanity
which was common to all the invaders - had made them objects of deadly hatred to the
inhabitants of the Peninsula. The wealth which had been accumulated during centuries of
prosperity and repose was rapidly melting away. The intellectual superiority of the
oppressed people only rendered them more keenly sensible of their political degradation.
Literature and taste, indeed, still disguised with a flush of hectic loveliness and
brilliancy the ravages of an incurable decay. The iron had not yet entered into the soul.
The time was not yet come when eloquence was to be gagged, and reason to be hoodwinked,
when the harp of the poet was to be hung on the willows of Arno, and the right hand of the
painter to forget its cunning. Yet a discerning eye might even then have seen that genius
and learning would not long survive the state of things from which they had sprung, and
that the great men whose talents gave lustre to that melancholy period had been formed
under the influence of happier days, and would leave no successors behind them. The times
which shine with the greatest splendor in literary history are not always those to which
the human mind is most indebted. Of this we may be convinced, by comparing the generation
which follows them with that which had preceded them. The first fruits which are reaped
under a bad system often spring from seed sown under a good one. Thus it was, in some
measure, with the Augustan age. Thus it was with the age of Raphael and Ariosto, of Aldus
and Vida.
Machiavelli deeply regretted the misfortunes of his country, and clearly discerned the
cause and the remedy. It was the military system of the Italian people which had
extinguished their valor and discipline, and left their wealth an easy prey to every
foreign plunderer. The secretary projected a scheme, alike honorable to his heart and to
his intellect, for abolishing the use of mercenary troops, and for organizing a national
militia.
The exertions which he made to effect this great object ought alone to rescue his name
from obloquy. Though his situation and his habits were pacific, he studied with intense
assiduity the theory of war. He made himself master of all its details. The Florentine
government entered into his views. A council of war was appointed. Levies were decreed.
The indefatigable minister flew from place to place in order to superintend the execution
of his design. The times were, in some respects, favorable to the experiment. The system
of military tactics had undergone a great revolution. The cavalry was no longer considered
as forming the strength of an army. The hours which a citizen could spare from his
ordinary employments, though by no means sufficient to familiarize him with the exercise
of a man-at-arms, might render him a useful foot-soldier. The dread of a foreign yoke, of
plunder, massacre, and conflagration, might have conquered that repugnance to military
pursuits which both the industry and the idleness of great towns commonly generate. For a
time the scheme promised well. The new troops acquitted themselves respectably in the
field. Machiavelli looked with parental rapture on the success of his plan, and began to
hope that the arms of Italy might once more be formidable to the barbarians of the Tagus
and the Rhine. But the tide of misfortune came on before the barriers which should have
withstood it were prepared. For a time, indeed, Florence might be considered as peculiarly
fortunate. Famine and sword and pestilence had devastated the fertile plains and stately
cities of the Po. All the curses denounced of old against Tyre seemed to have fallen on
Venice. Her merchants already stood afar off, lamenting for their great city. The time
seemed near when the sea-weed should overgrow her silent Rialto, and the fisherman wash
his nets in her deserted arsenal. Naples had been four times conquered and reconquered by
tyrants equally indifferent to its welfare, and equally greedy for its spoils. Florence,
as yet, had only to endure degradation and extortion, to submit to the mandates of foreign
powers, to buy over and over again, at an enormous price, what was already justly her own,
to return thanks for being wronged, and to ask pardon for being in the right. She was at
length deprived of the blessings, even of this infamous and servile repose. Her military
and political institutions were swept away together. The Medici returned, in the train of
foreign invaders, from their long exile. The policy of Machiavelli was abandoned; and his
public services were requited with poverty, imprisonment, and torture.
The fallen statesman still clung to his project with unabated ardor. With the view of
vindicating it from some popular objections, and of refuting some prevailing errors on the
subject of military science, he wrote his "Seven Books on the Art of War." This
excellent work is in the form of a dialogue. The opinions of the writer are put into the
mouth of Fabrizio Colonna, a powerful nobleman of the ecclesiastical State, and an officer
of distinguished merit in the service of the King of Spain. Colonna visits Florence on his
way from Lombardy to his own domains. He is invited to meet some friends at the house of
Cosimo Rucellai, an amiable and accomplished young man, whose early death Machiavelli
feelingly deplores. After partaking of an elegant entertainment, they retire from the heat
into the most shady recesses of the garden. Fabrizio is struck by the sight of some
uncommon plants. Cosimo says, that, though rare in modern days, they are frequently
mentioned by the classical authors, and that his grandfather, like many other Italians,
amused himself with practising the ancient methods of gardening. Fabrizio expresses his
regret that those who, in later times, affected the manners of the old Romans, should
select for imitation the most trifling pursuits. This leads to a conversation on the
decline of military discipline, and on the best means of restoring it. The institution of
the Florentine militia is ably defended, and several improvements are suggested in the
details.
The Swiss and the Spaniards were, at that time, regarded as the best soldiers in
Europe. The Swiss battalion consisted of pikemen, and bore a close resemblance to the
Greek phalanx. The Spaniards, like the soldiers of Rome, were armed with the sword and the
shield. The victories of Flaminius and Aemilius over the Macedonian kings seem to prove
the superiority of the weapons used by the legions. The same experiment had been recently
tried with the same result at the battle of Ravenna, one of those tremendous days into
which human folly and wickedness compress the whole devastation of a famine or a plague.
In that memorable conflict, the infantry of Aragon, the old companions of Gonsalvo,
deserted by all their allies, hewed a passage through the thickest of the imperial pikes,
and effected an unbroken retreat, in the face of the gendarmerie of De Foix, and the
renowned artillery of Este. Fabrizio, or rather Machiavelli, proposes to combine the two
systems, to arm the foremost lines with the pike for the purpose of repulsing cavalry, and
those in the rear with the sword, as being a weapon better adapted for every other
purpose. Throughout the work, the author expresses the highest admiration of the military
science of the ancient Romans, and the greatest contempt for the maxims which had been in
vogue amongst the Italian commanders of the preceding generation. He prefers infantry to
cavalry, and fortified camps to fortified towns. He is inclined to substitute rapid
movements and decisive engagements for the languid and dilatory operations of his
countrymen. He attaches very little importance to the invention of gunpowder. Indeed, he
seems to think that it ought scarcely to produce any change in the mode of arming or of
disposing troops. The general testimony of historians, it must be allowed, seems to prove
that the ill-constructed and ill-served artillery of those times, though useful in a
siege, was of little value on the field of battle.
On the tactics of Machiavelli we will not venture to give an opinion, but we are
certain that his book is most able and interesting. As a commentary on the history of his
times, it is invaluable. The ingenuity, the grace, and the perspicuity of the style, and
the eloquence and animation of particular passages, must give pleasure, even to readers
who take no interest in the subject.
"The Prince" and the "Discourses on Livy" were written after the
fall of the republican government. The former was dedicated to the young Lorenzo de'
Medici. This circumstance seems to have disgusted the contemporaries of the writer far
more that the doctrines which have rendered the name of the work odious in latter times.
It was considered as an indication of political apostasy. The fact, however, seems to have
been, that Machiavelli, despairing of the liberty of Florence, was inclined to support any
government which might preserve her independence. The interval which separated a democracy
and a despotism Soderini and Lorenzo, seemed to vanish when compared with the difference
between the former and the present state of Italy, between the security, the opulence, and
the repose which she had enjoyed under its native rulers, and the misery in which she had
been plunged since the fatal year in which the first foreign tyrant had descended from the
Alps. The noble and pathetic exhortation with which "The Prince" concludes shows
how strongly the writer felt upon this subject.
"The Prince" traces the progress of an ambitious man, the
"Discourses" the progress of an ambitious people. The same principles on which,
in the former work, the elevation of an individual is explained, are applied, in the
latter, to the longer duration and more complex interest of a society. To a modern
statesman the form of the "Discourses" may appear to be puerile. In truth, Livy
is not a historian on whom implicit reliance can be placed, even in cases where he must
have possessed considerable means of information. And the first Decade, to which
Machiavelli has confined himself, is scarcely entitled to more credit than our Chronicle
of British Kings who reigned before the Roman invasion. But the commentator is indebted to
Livy for little more than a few texts which he might as easily have extracted from the
Vulgate or "The Decameron." The whole train of thought is original.
On the peculiar immorality which has rendered "The Prince" unpopular, and
which is almost equally discernible in the "Discourses" we have already given
our opinion at length. We have attempted to show that it belonged rather to the age than
to the man, that it was a partial taint, and by no means implied general depravity. We
cannot, however, deny that it is a great blemish, and that it considerably diminishes the
pleasure which, in other respects, those works must afford to every intelligent mind.
It is, indeed, impossible to conceive a more healthful and vigorous constitution of the
understanding than that which these works indicate. The qualities of the active and the
contemplative statesman appear to have been blended in the mind of the writer into a rare
and exquisite harmony. His skill in the details of business had not been acquired at the
expense of his general powers. It had not rendered his mind less comprehensive; but it had
served to correct his speculations, and to impart to them that vivid and practical
character which so widely distinguishes them from the vague theories of most political
philosophers.
Every man who has seen the world knows that nothing is so useless as a general maxim.
If it be very moral and very true, it may serve for a copy to a charity boy. If, like
those of Rochefoucauld, it be sparkling and whimsical, it may make an excellent motto for
an essay. But few indeed of the many wise apophthegms which have been uttered, from the
time of the Seven Sages of Greece to that of "Poor Richard," have prevented a
single foolish action. We give the highest and the most peculiar praise to the precepts of
Machiavelli when we say that they may frequently be of real use in regulating conduct, not
so much because they are more just or more profound than those which might be culled from
other authors, as because they can be more readily applied to the problems of real life.
There are errors in these works. But they are errors which a writer, situated like
Machiavelli, could scarcely avoid. They arise, for the most part, from a single defect
which appears to us to pervade his whole system. In his political scheme, the means had
been more deeply considered than the ends. The great principle, that societies and laws
exist only for the purpose of increasing the sum of private happiness, is not recognized
with sufficient clearness. The good of the body, distinct from the good of the members,
and sometimes hardly compatible with the good of the members, seems to be the object which
he proposes to himself. Of all political fallacies, this has perhaps had the widest and
the most mischievous operation. The state of society in the little commonwealths of
Greece, the close connection and mutual dependence of the citizens, and the severity of
the laws of war, tended to encourage an opinion which, under such circumstances, could
hardly be called erroneous. The interests of every individual were inseparably bound up
with those of the State. An invasion destroyed his corn-fields and vineyards, drove him
from his home, and compelled him to encounter all the hardships of a military life. A
treaty of peace restored him to security and comfort. A victory doubled the number of his
slaves. A defeat perhaps made him a slave himself. When Pericles, in the Peloponnesian
war, told the Athenians, that, if their country triumphed, their private losses would
speedily be repaired, but that, if their arms failed of success, every individual amongst
them would probably be ruined, he spoke no more than the truth. He spoke to men whom the
tribute of vanquished cities supplied with food and clothing, with the luxury of the bath
and the amusements of the theatre, on whom the greatness of their country conferred rank,
and before whom the members of less prosperous communities trembled; to men who, in case
of a change in the public fortunes, would, at least, be deprived of every comfort and
every distinction which they enjoyed. To be butchered on the smoking ruins of their city,
to be dragged in chains to a slave-market, to see one child torn from them to dig in the
quarries of Sicily, and another to guard the harems of Persepolis, these were the frequent
and probable consequences of national calamities. Hence, among the Greeks, patriotism
became a governing principle, or rather an ungovernable passion. Their legislators and
their philosophers took it for granted, that, in providing for the strength and greatness
of the State, they sufficiently provided for the happiness of the people. The writers of
the Roman Empire lived under despots, into whose dominion a hundred nations were melted
down, and whose gardens would have covered the little commonwealths of Phlius and Plataea.
Yet they continued to employ the same language, and to cant about the duty of sacrificing
everything to a country to which they owed nothing.
Causes similar to those which had influenced the disposition of the Greeks operated
powerfully on the less vigorous and daring character of the Italians. The Italians, like
the Greeks, were members of small communities. Every man was deeply interested in the
welfare of the society to which he belonged, a partaker in its wealth and its poverty, in
its glory and its shame. In the age of Machiavelli this was peculiarly the case. Public
events had produced an immense sum of misery to private citizens. The Northern invaders
had brought want to their boards, infamy to their beds, fire to their roofs, and the knife
to their throats. It was natural that a man who lived in times like these should overrate
the importance of those measures by which a nation is rendered formidable to its
neighbors, and undervalue those which make it prosperous within itself.
Nothing is more remarkable in the political treatises of Machiavelli than the fairness
of mind which they indicate. It appears where the author is in the wrong, almost as
strongly as where he is in the right. He never advances a false opinion because it is new
or splendid, because he can clothe it in a happy phrase, or defend it by an ingenious
sophism. His errors are at once explained by a reference to the circumstances in which he
was placed. They evidently were not sought out: they lay in his way, and could scarcely be
avoided. Such mistakes must necessarily be committed by early speculators in every
science.
The political works of Machiavelli derive a peculiar interest from the mournful
earnestness which he manifests whenever he touches on topics connected with the calamities
of his native land. It is difficult to conceive any situation more painful that of a great
man, condemned to watch the lingering agony of an exhausted country, to tend it during the
alternate fits of stupefaction and raving which precede its dissolution, and to see the
symptoms of vitality disappear one by one, till nothing is left but coldness, darkness,
and corruption. To this joyless and thankless duty was Machiavelli called. In the
energetic language of the prophet, he was "mad for the sight of his eyes which he
saw" - disunion in the Council, effeminacy in the camp, liberty extinguished,
commerce decaying, national honor sullied, an enlightened and flourishing people given
over to the ferocity of ignorant savages. Though his opinions had not escaped the
contagion of that political immorality which was common among his countrymen, his natural
disposition seems to have been rather stern and impetuous than pliant and artful. When the
misery and degradation of Florence, and the foul outrage which he had himself sustained,
recur to his mind, the smooth craft of his profession and his nation is exchanged for the
honest bitterness of scorn and anger. He speaks like one sick of the calamitous times and
abject people among whom his lot is cast. He pines for the strength and glory of ancient
Rome, for the fasces of Brutus and the sword of Scipio, the gravity of the curule chair,
and the bloody pomp of the triumphal sacrifice. He seems to be transported back to the
days when 800,000 Italian warriors sprung to arms at the rumor of a Gallic invasion. He
breathes all the spirit of those intrepid and haughty Senators who forgot the dearest ties
of nature in the claims of public duty, who looked with disdain on the elephants and on
the gold of Pyrrhus, and listened with unaltered composure to the tremendous tidings of
Cannae. Like an ancient temple deformed by the barbarous architecture of a later age, his
character acquires an interest from the very circumstances which debase it. The original
proportions are rendered more striking by the contrast which they present to the mean and
incongruous additions.
The influence of the sentiments which we have described was not apparent in his
writings alone. His enthusiasm, barred from the career which it would have selected for
itself, seems to have found a vent in desperate levity. He enjoyed a vindictive pleasure
in outraging the opinions of a society which he despised. He became careless of the
decencies which were expected from a man so highly distinguished in the literary and
political world. The sarcastic bitterness of his conversation disgusted those who were
more inclined to accuse his licentiousness than their own degeneracy, and who were unable
to conceive the strength of those emotions which are concealed by the jests of the
wretched, and by the follies of the wise.
The historical works of Machiavelli still remain to be considered. The life of
Castruccio Castracani will occupy us for a very short time, and would scarcely have
demanded our notice had it not attracted a much greater share of public attention than it
deserves. Few books, indeed, could be more interesting than a careful and judicious
account, from such a pen, of the illustrious Prince of Lucca, the most eminent of those
Italian chiefs, who, like Pisistratus and Gelon, acquired a power felt rather than seen,
and resting, not on law or on prescription, but on the public favor and on their great
personal qualities. Such a work would exhibit to us the real nature of that species of
sovereignty, so singular and so often misunderstood, which the Greeks denominated tyranny,
and which, modified in some degree by the feudal system, reappeared in the commonwealths
of Lombardy and Tuscany. But this little composition of Machiavelli is in no sense a
history. It has no pretensions to fidelity. It is trifle, and not a very successful
trifle. It is scarcely more authentic than the novel of "Belphegor," and is very
much duller.
The last great work of this illustrious man was the history of his native city. It was
written by command of the Pope, who, as chief of the house of Medici, was at that time
sovereign of Florence. The characters of Cosimo, of Piero, and of Lorenzo, are, however,
treated with a freedom and impartiality equally honorable to the writer and to the patron.
The miseries and humiliations of dependence, the bread which is more bitter than every
other food, the stairs which are more painful than every other ascent, has not broken the
spirit of Machiavelli. The most corrupting post in a corrupting profession had not
depraved the generous heart of Clement.
The history does not appear to be the fruit of much industry or research. It is
unquestionably inaccurate. But it is elegant, lively, and picturesque, beyond any other in
the Italian language. The reader, we believe, carries away from it a more vivid and a more
faithful impression of the national character and manners than from more correct accounts.
The truth is, that the book belongs rather to ancient than to modern literature. It is in
the style, not of Davila and Clarendon, but of Herodotus and Tacitus. The classical
histories may almost be called romances founded in fact. The relation is, no doubt, in all
its principel points, strictly true. But the numerous little incidents which heighten the
interest, the words, the gestures, the looks, are evidently furnished by the imagination
of the author. The fashion of later times is different. A more exact narrative is given by
the writer.
It may be doubted whether more exact notions are conveyed to the reader. The best
portraits are perhaps those in which there is a slight mixture of caricature, and we are
not certain that the best histories are not those in which a little of the exaggeration of
fictitious narrative is judiciously employed. Something is lost in accuracy, but much is
gained in effect. The fainter lines are neglected, but the great characteristic features
are imprinted on the mind forever.
The history terminates with the death of Lorenzo de' Medici. Machiavelli had, it seems,
intended to continue his narrative to a later period. But his death prevented the
execution of his design, and the melancholy task of recording the desolation and shame of
Italy devolved on Guicciardini.
Machiavelli lived long enough to see the commencement of the last struggle for
Florentine liberty. Soon after his death monarchy was finally established, not such a
monarchy as that of which Cosimo had laid the foundations deep in the institutions and
feelings of his countrymen, and which Lorenzo had embellished with the trophies of every
science and every art, but a loathsome tyranny, proud and mean, cruel and feeble, bigoted
and lascivious. The character of Machiavelli was hateful to the new masters of Italy, and
those parts of his theory which were in strict accordance with their own daily practice
afforded a pretext for blackening his memory. His works were misrepresented by the
learned, misconstrued by the ignorant, censured by the Church, abused with all the rancor
of simulated virtue by the tools of a base government and the priests of a baser
superstition. The name of the man whose genius had illuminated all the dark places of
policy, and to whose patriotic wisdom an oppressed people had owed their last chance of
emancipation and revenge, passed into a proverb of infamy. For more than two hundred years
his bones lay undistinguished. At length an English nobleman paid the last honors to the
greatest statesman of Florence. In the Church of Santa Croce a monument was erected to his
memory, which is contemplated with reverence by all who can distinguish the virtues of a
great mind through the corruptions of a degenerate age, and which will be approached with
still deeper homage when the object to which his public life was devoted shall be
attained, when the foreign yoke shall be broken, when a second Procida shall avenge the
wrongs of Naples, when a happier Rienzi shall restore the good estate of Rome, when the
streets of Florence and Bologna shall again resound with their ancient war cry,
"Popolo; popolo; muoiano i tiranni!"10
[Footnote 10: "The people! the people! Death to the tyrants!" - Machiavelli's
"History of Florence, " Book III.]