Modern History Sourcebook:
John Stuart Mill:
On Liberty
CHAPTER I INTRODUCTORY
THE subject of this Essay is not the so-called Liberty of the
Will, so unfortunately opposed to the misnamed doctrine of Philosophical
Necessity; but Civil, or Social Liberty: the nature and limits
of the power which can be legitimately exercised by society over
the individual. A question seldom stated, and hardly ever discussed,
in general terms, but which profoundly influences the practical
controversies of the age by its latent presence, and is likely
soon to make itself recognized as the vital question of the future.
It is so far from being new, that, in a certain sense, it has
divided mankind, almost from the remotest ages, but in the stage
of progress into which the more civilized portions of the species
have now entered, it presents itself under new conditions, and
requires a different and more fundamental treatment.
The struggle between Liberty and Authority is the most conspicuous
feature in the portions of history with which we are earliest
familiar, particularly in that of Greece, Rome, and England. But
in old times this contest was between subjects, or some classes
of subjects, and the government. By liberty, was meant protection
against the tyranny of the political rulers. The rulers were conceived
(except in some of the popular governments of Greece) as in a
necessarily antagonistic position to the people whom they ruled.
They consisted of a governing One, or a governing tribe or caste,
who derived their authority from inheritance or conquest; who,
at all events, did not hold it at the pleasure of the governed,
and whose supremacy men did not venture, perhaps did not desire,
to contest, whatever precautions might be taken against its oppressive
exercise. Their power was regarded as necessary, but also as highly
dangerous; as a weapon which they would attempt to use against
their subjects, no less than against external enemies. To prevent
the weaker members of the community from being preyed upon by
innumerable vultures, it was needful that there should be an animal
of prey stronger than the rest, commissioned to keep them down.
But as the king of the vultures would be no less bent upon preying
upon the flock than any of the minor harpies, it was indispensable
to be in a perpetual attitude of defence against his beak and
claws. The aim, therefore, of patriots, was to set limits to the
power which the ruler should be suffered to exercise over the
community; and this limitation was what they meant by liberty.
It was attempted in two ways. First, by obtaining a recognition
of certain immunities, called political liberties or rights, which
it was to be regarded as a breach of duty in the ruler to infringe,
and which, if he did infringe, specific resistance, or general
rebellion, was held to be justifiable. A second, and generally
a later expedient, was the establishment of constitutional checks;
by which the consent of the community, or of a body of some sort
supposed to represent its interests, was made a necessary condition
to some of the more important acts of the governing power. To
the first of these modes of limitation, the ruling power, in most
European countries, was compelled, more or less, to submit. It
was not so with the second; and to attain this, or when already
in some degree possessed, to attain it more completely, became
everywhere the principal object of the lovers of liberty. And
so long as mankind were content to combat one enemy by another,
and to be ruled by a master, on condition of being guaranteed
more or less efficaciously against his tyranny, they did not carry
their aspirations beyond this point.
A time, however, came in the progress of human affairs, when men
ceased to think it a necessity of nature that their governors
should be an independent power, opposed in interest to themselves.
It appeared to them much better that the various magistrates of
the State should be their tenants or delegates, revocable at their
pleasure. In that way alone, it seemed, could they have complete
security that the powers of government would never be abused to
their disadvantage. By degrees, this new demand for elective and
temporary rulers became the prominent object of the exertions
of the popular party, wherever any such party existed; and superseded,
to a considerable extent, the previous efforts to limit the power
of rulers. As the struggle proceeded for making the ruling power
emanate from the periodical choice of the ruled, some persons
began to think that too much importance had been attached to the
limitation of the power itself. That (it might seem) was a resource
against rulers whose interests were habitually opposed to those
of the people. What was now wanted was, that the rulers should
be identified with the people; that their interest and will should
be the interest and will of the nation. The nation did not need
to be protected against its own will. There was no fear of its
tyrannizing over itself. Let the rulers be effectually responsible
to it, promptly removable by it, and it could afford to trust
them with power of which it could itself dictate the use to be
made. Their power was but the nation's own power, concentrated,
and in a form convenient for exercise. This mode of thought, or
rather perhaps of feeling, was common among the last generation
of European liberalism, in the Continental section of which, it
still apparently predominates. Those who admit any limit to what
a government may do, except in the case of such governments as
they think ought not to exist, stand out as brilliant exceptions
among the political thinkers of the Continent. A similar tone
of sentiment might by this time have been prevalent in our own
country, if the circumstances which for a time encouraged it had
continued unaltered.
But, in political and philosophical theories, as well as in persons,
success discloses faults and infirmities which failure might have
concealed from observation. The notion, that the people have no
need to limit their power over themselves, might seem axiomatic,
when popular government was a thing only dreamed about, or read
of as having existed at some distant period of the past. Neither
was that notion necessarily disturbed by such temporary aberrations
as those of the French Revolution, the worst of which were the
work of an usurping few, and which, in any case, belonged, not
to the permanent working of popular institutions, but to a sudden
and convulsive outbreak against monarchical and aristocratic despotism.
In time, however, a democratic republic came to occupy a large
portion of the earth's surface, and made itself felt as one of
the most powerful members of the community of nations; and elective
and responsible government became subject to the observations
and criticisms which wait upon a great existing fact. It was now
perceived that such phrases as "self-government," and
"the power of the people over themselves," do not express
the true state of the case. The "people" who exercise
the power, are not always the same people with those over whom
it is exercised, and the "self-government" spoken of,
is not the government of each by himself, but of each by all the
rest. The will of the people, moreover, practically means, the
will of the most numerous or the most active part of the people;
the majority, or those who succeed in making themselves accepted
as the majority; the people, consequently, may desire to oppress
a part of their number; and precautions are as much needed against
this, as against any other abuse of power. The limitation, therefore,
of the power of government over individuals, loses none of its
importance when the holders of power are regularly accountable
to the community, that is, to the strongest party therein. This
view of things, recommending itself equally to the intelligence
of thinkers and to the inclination of those important classes
in European society to whose real or supposed interests democracy
is adverse, has had no difficulty in establishing itself; and
in political speculations "the tyranny of the majority"
is now generally included among the evils against which society
requires to be on its guard.
Like other tyrannies, the tyranny of the majority was at first,
and is still vulgarly, held in dread, chiefly as operating through
the acts of the public authorities. But reflecting persons perceived
that when society is itself the tyrant --society collectively,
over the separate individuals who compose it--its means of tyrannizing
are not restricted to the acts which it may do by the hands of
its political functionaries. Society can and does execute its
own mandates: and if it issues wrong mandates instead of right,
or any mandates at all in things with which it ought not to meddle,
it practises a social tyranny more formidable than many kinds
of political oppression, since, though not usually upheld by such
extreme penalties, it leaves fewer means of escape, penetrating
much more deeply into the details of life, and enslaving the soul
itself. Protection, therefore, against the tyranny of the magistrate
is not enough; there needs protection also against the tyranny
of the prevailing opinion and feeling; against the tendency of
society to impose, by other means than civil penalties, its own
ideas and practices as rules of conduct on those who dissent from
them; to fetter the development, and, if possible, prevent the
formation, of any individuality not in harmony with its ways,
and compel all characters to fashion themselves upon the model
of its own. There is a limit to the legitimate interference of
collective opinion with individual independence; and to find that
limit, and maintain it against encroachment, is as indispensable
to a good condition of human affairs, as protection against political
despotism.
But though this proposition is not likely to be contested in general
terms, the practical question, where to place the limit--how to
make the fitting adjustment between individual independence and
social control--is a subject on which nearly everything remains
to be done. All that makes existence valuable to any one, depends
on the enforcement of restraints upon the actions of other people.
Some rules of conduct, therefore, must be imposed, by law in the
first place, and by opinion on many things which are not fit subjects
for the operation of law. What these rules should be, is the principal
question in human affairs; but if we except a few of the most
obvious cases, it is one of those which least progress has been
made in resolving. No two ages, and scarcely any two countries,
have decided it alike; and the decision of one age or country
is a wonder to another. Yet the people of any given age and country
no more suspect any difficulty in it, than if it were a subject
on which mankind had always been agreed. The rules which obtain
among themselves appear to them self-evident and selfjustifying.
This all but universal illusion is one of the examples of the
magical influence of custom, which is not only, as the proverb
says a second nature, but is continually mistaken for the first.
The effect of custom, in preventing any misgiving respecting the
rules of conduct which mankind impose on one another, is all the
more complete because the subJect is one on which it is not generally
considered necessary that reasons should be given, either by one
person to others, or by each to himself. People are accustomed
to believe and have been encouraged in the belief by some who
aspire to the character of philosophers, that their feelings,
on subjects of this nature, are better than reasons, and render
reasons unnecessary. The practical principle which guides them
to their opinions on the regulation of human conduct, is the feeling
in each person's mind that everybody should be required to act
as he, and those with whom he sympathizes, would like them to
act. No one, indeed, acknowledges to himself that his standard
of judgment is his own liking; but an opinion on a point of conduct,
not supported by reasons, can only count as one person's preference;
and if the reasons, when given, are a mere appeal to a similar
preference felt by other people, it is still only many people's
liking instead of one. To an ordinary man, however, his own preference,
thus supported, is not only a perfectly satisfactory reason, but
the only one he generally has for any of his notions of morality,
taste, or propriety, which are not expressly written in his religious
creed; and his chief guide in the interpretation even of that.
Men's opinions, accordingly, on what is laudable or blamable,
are affected by all the multifarious causes which influence their
wishes in regard to the conduct of others, and which are as numerous
as those which determine their wishes on any other subject. Sometimes
their reason--at other times their prejudices or superstitions:
often their social affections, not seldom their antisocial ones,
their envy or jealousy, their arrogance or contemptuousness: but
most commonly, their desires or fears for themselves--their legitimate
or illegitimate self-interest. Wherever there is an ascendant
class, a large portion of the morality of the country emanates
from its class interests, and its feelings of class superiority.
The morality between Spartans and Helots, between planters and
negroes, between princes and subjects, between nobles and roturiers,
between men and women, has been for the most part the creation
of these class interests and feelings: and the sentiments thus
generated, react in turn upon the moral feelings of the members
of the ascendant class, in their relations among themselves. Where,
on the other hand, a class, formerly ascendant, has lost its ascendency,
or where its ascendency is unpopular, the prevailing moral sentiments
frequently bear the impress of an impatient dislike of superiority.
Another grand determining principle of the rules of conduct, both
in act and forbearance which have been enforced by law or opinion,
has been the servility of mankind towards the supposed preferences
or aversions of their temporal masters, or of their gods. This
servility though essentially selfish, is not hypocrisy; it gives
rise to perfectly genuine sentiments of abhorrence; it made men
burn magicians and heretics. Among so many baser influences, the
general and obvious interests of society have of course had a
share, and a large one, in the direction of the moral sentiments:
less, however, as a matter of reason, and on their own account,
than as a consequence of the sympathies and antipathies which
grew out of them: and sympathies and antipathies which had little
or nothing to do with the interests of society, have made themselves
felt in the establishment of moralities with quite as great force.
The likings and dislikings of society, or of some powerful portion
of it, are thus the main thing which has practically determined
the rules laid down for general observance, under the penalties
of law or opinion. And in general, those who have been in advance
of society in thought and feeling, have left this condition of
things unassailed in principle, however they may have come into
conflict with it in some of its details. They have occupied themselves
rather in inquiring what things society ought to like or dislike,
than in questioning whether its likings or dislikings should be
a law to individuals. They preferred endeavouring to alter the
feelings of mankind on the particular points on which they were
themselves heretical, rather than make common cause in defence
of freedom, with heretics generally. The only case in which the
higher ground has been taken on principle and maintained with
consistency, by any but an individual here and there, is that
of religious belief: a case instructive in many ways, and not
least so as forming a most striking instance of the fallibility
of what is called the moral sense: for the odium theologicum,
in a sincere bigot, is one of the most unequivocal cases of moral
feeling. Those who first broke the yoke of what called itself
the Universal Church, were in general as little willing to permit
difference of religious opinion as that church itself. But when
the heat of the conflict was over, without giving a complete victory
to any party, and each church or sect was reduced to limit its
hopes to retaining possession of the ground it already occupied;
minorities, seeing that they had no chance of becoming majorities,
were under the necessity of pleading to those whom they could
not convert, for permission to differ. It is accordingly on this
battle-field, almost solely, that the rights of the individual
against society have been asserted on broad grounds of principle,
and the claim of society to exercise authority over dissentients
openly controverted. The great writers to whom the world owes
what religious liberty it possesses, have mostly asserted freedom
of conscience as an indefeasible right, and denied absolutely
that a human being is accountable to others for his religious
belief. Yet so natural to mankind is intolerance in whatever they
really care about, that religious freedom has hardly anywhere
been practically realized, except where religious indifference,
which dislikes to have its peace disturbed by theological quarrels,
has added its weight to the scale. In the minds of almost all
religious persons, even in the most tolerant countries, the duty
of toleration is admitted with tacit reserves. One person will
bear with dissent in matters of church government, but not of
dogma; another can tolerate everybody, short of a Papist or an
Unitarian; another, every one who believes in revealed religion;
a few extend their charity a little further, but stop at the belief
in a God and in a future state. Wherever the sentiment of the
majority is still genuine and intense, it is found to have abated
little of its claim to be obeyed.
In England, from the peculiar circumstances of our political history,
though the yoke of opinion is perhaps heavier, that of law is
lighter, than in most other countries of Europe; and there is
considerable jealousy of direct interference, by the legislative
or the executive power with private conduct; not so much from
any just regard for the independence of the individual, as from
the still subsisting habit of looking on the government as representing
an opposite interest to the public. The majority have not yet
learnt to feel the power of the government their power, or its
opinions their opinions. When they do so, individual liberty will
probably be as much exposed to invasion from the government, as
it already is from public opinion. But, as yet, there is a considerable
amount of feeling ready to be called forth against any attempt
of the law to control individuals in things in which they have
not hitherto been accustomed to be controlled by it; and this
with very little discrimination as to whether the matter is, or
is not, within the legitimate sphere of legal control; insomuch
that the feeling, highly salutary on the whole, is perhaps quite
as often misplaced as well grounded in the particular instances
of its application.
There is, in fact, no recognized principle by which the propriety
or impropriety of government interference is customarily tested.
People decide according to their personal preferences. Some, whenever
they see any good to be done, or evil to be remedied, would willingly
instigate the government to undertake the business; while others
prefer to bear almost any amount of social evil, rather than add
one to the departments of human interests amenable to governmental
control. And men range themselves on one or the other side in
any particular case, according to this general direction of their
sentiments; or according to the degree of interest which they
feel in the particular thing which it is proposed that the government
should do; or according to the belief they entertain that the
government would, or would not, do it in the manner they prefer;
but very rarely on account of any opinion to which they consistently
adhere, as to what things are fit to be done by a government.
And it seems to me that, in consequence of this absence of rule
or principle, one side is at present as often wrong as the other;
the interference of government is, with about equal frequency,
improperly invoked and improperly condemned.
The object of this Essay is to assert one very simple principle,
as entitled to govern absolutely the dealings of society with
the individual in the way of compulsion and control, whether the
means used be physical force in the form of legal penalties, or
the moral coercion of public opinion. That principle is, that
the sole end for which mankind are warranted, individually or
collectively in interfering with the liberty of action of any
of their number, is self-protection. That the only purpose for
which power can be rightfully exercised over any member of a civilized
community, against his will, is to prevent harm to others. His
own good, either physical or moral, is not a sufficient warrant.
He cannot rightfully be compelled to do or forbear because it
will be better for him to do so, because it will make him happier,
because, in the opinions of others, to do so would be wise, or
even right. These are good reasons for remonstrating with him,
or reasoning with him, or persuading him, or entreating him, but
not for compelling him, or visiting him with any evil, in case
he do otherwise. To justify that, the conduct from which it is
desired to deter him must be calculated to produce evil to some
one else. The only part of the conduct of any one, for which he
is amenable to society, is that which concerns others. In the
part which merely concerns himself, his independence is, of right,
absolute. Over himself, over his own body and mind, the individual
is sovereign.
It is, perhaps, hardly necessary to say that this doctrine is
meant to apply only to human beings in the maturity of their faculties.
We are not speaking of children, or of young persons below the
age which the law may fix as that of manhood or womanhood. Those
who are still in a state to require being taken care of by others,
must be protected against their own actions as well as against
external injury. For the same reason, we may leave out of consideration
those backward states of society in which the race itself may
be considered as in its nonage. The early difficulties in the
way of spontaneous progress are so great, that there is seldom
any choice of means for overcoming them; and a ruler full of the
spirit of improvement is warranted in the use of any expedients
that will attain an end, perhaps otherwise unattainable. Despotism
is a legitimate mode of government in dealing with barbarians,
provided the end be their improvement, and the means justified
by actually effecting that end. Liberty, as a principle, has no
application to any state of things anterior to the time when mankind
have become capable of being improved by free and equal discussion.
Until then, there is nothing for them but implicit obedience to
an Akbar or a Charlemagne, if they are so fortunate as to find
one. But as soon as mankind have attained the capacity of being
guided to their own improvement by conviction or persuasion (a
period long since reached in all nations with whom we need here
concern ourselves), compulsion, either in the direct form or in
that of pains and penalties for non-compliance, is no longer admissible
as a means to their own good, and justifiable only for the security
of others.
It is proper to state that I forego any advantage which could
be derived to my argument from the idea of abstract right as a
thing independent of utility. I regard utility as the ultimate
appeal on all ethical questions; but it must be utility in the
largest sense, grounded on the permanent interests of man as a
progressive being. Those interests, I contend, authorize the subjection
of individual spontaneity to external control, only in respect
to those actions of each, which concern the interest of other
people. If any one does an act hurtful to others, there is a prima
facie case for punishing him, by law, or, where legal penalties
are not safely applicable, by general disapprobation. There are
also many positive acts for the benefit of others, which he may
rightfully be compelled to perform; such as, to give evidence
in a court of justice; to bear his fair share in the common defence,
or in any other joint work necessary to the interest of the society
of which he enjoys the protection; and to perform certain acts
of individual beneficence, such as saving a fellow-creature's
life, or interposing to protect the defenceless against ill-usage,
things which whenever it is obviously a man's duty to do, he may
rightfully be made responsible to society for not doing. A person
may cause evil to others not only by his actions but by his inaction,
and in neither case he is justly accountable to them for the injury.
The latter case, it is true, requires a much more cautious exercise
of compulsion than the former. To make any one answerable for
doing evil to others, is the rule; to make him answerable for
not preventing evil, is, comparatively speaking, the exception.
Yet there are many cases clear enough and grave enough to justify
that exception. In all things which regard the external relations
of the individual, he is de jure amenable to those whose interests
are concerned, and if need be, to society as their protector.
There are often good reasons for not holding him to the responsibility;
but these reasons must arise from the special expediencies of
the case: either because it is a kind of case in which he is on
the whole likely to act better, when left to his own discretion,
than when controlled in any way in which society have it in their
power to control him; or because the attempt to exercise control
would produce other evils, greater than those which it would prevent.
When such reasons as these preclude the enforcement of responsibility,
the conscience of the agent himself should step into the vacant
judgment-seat, and protect those interests of others which have
no external protection; judging himself all the more rigidly,
because the case does not admit of his being made accountable
to the judgment of his fellowcreatures.
But there is a sphere of action in which society, as distinguished
from the individual, has, if any, only an indirect interest; comprehending
all that portion of a person's life and conduct which affects
only himself, or, if it also affects others, only with their free,
voluntary, and undeceived consent and participation. When I say
only himself, I mean directly, and in the first instance: for
whatever affects himself, may affect others through himself; and
the objection which may be grounded on this contingency, will
receive consideration in the sequel. This, then, is the appropriate
region of human liberty. It comprises, first, the inward domain
of consciousness; demanding liberty of conscience, in the most
comprehensive sense; liberty of thought and feeling; absolute
freedom of opinion and sentiment on all subjects, practical or
speculative, scientific, moral, or theological. The liberty of
expressing and publishing opinions may seem to fall under a different
principle, since it belongs to that part of the conduct of an
individual which concerns other people; but, being almost of as
much importance as the liberty of thought itself, and resting
in great part on the same reasons, is practically inseparable
from it. Secondly, the principle requires liberty of tastes and
pursuits; of framing the plan of our life to suit our own character;
of doing as we like, subject to such consequences as may follow;
without impediment from our fellow-creatures, so long as what
we do does not harm them even though they should think our conduct
foolish, perverse, or wrong. Thirdly, from this liberty of each
individual, follows the liberty, within the same limits, of combination
among individuals; freedom to unite, for any purpose not involving
harm to others: the persons combining being supposed to be of
full age, and not forced or deceived.
No society in which these liberties are not, on the whole, respected,
is free, whatever may be its form of government; and none is completely
free in which they do not exist absolute and unqualified. The
only freedom which deserves the name, is that of pursuing our
own good in our own way, so long as we do not attempt to deprive
others of theirs, or impede their efforts to obtain it. Each is
the proper guardian of his own health, whether bodily, or mental
or spiritual. Mankind are greater gainers by suffering each other
to live as seems good to themselves, than by compelling each to
live as seems good to the rest.
Though this doctrine is anything but new, and, to some persons,
may have the air of a truism, there is no doctrine which stands
more directly opposed to the general tendency of existing opinion
and practice. Society has expended fully as much effort in the
attempt (according to its lights) to compel people to conform
to its notions of personal, as of social excellence. The ancient
commonwealths thought themselves entitled to practise, and the
ancient philosophers countenanced, the regulation of every part
of private conduct by public authority, on the ground that the
State had a deep interest in the whole bodily and mental discipline
of every one of its citizens, a mode of thinking which may have
been admissible in small republics surrounded by powerful enemies,
in constant peril of being subverted by foreign attack or internal
commotion, and to which even a short interval of relaxed energy
and self-command might so easily be fatal, that they could not
afford to wait for the salutary permanent effects of freedom.
In the modern world, the greater size of political communities,
and above all, the separation between the spiritual and temporal
authority (which placed the direction of men's consciences in
other hands than those which controlled their worldly affairs),
prevented so great an interference by law in the details of private
life; but the engines of moral repression have been wielded more
strenuously against divergence from the reigning opinion in self-regarding,
than even in social matters; religion, the most powerful of the
elements which have entered into the formation of moral feeling,
having almost always been governed either by the ambition of a
hierarchy, seeking control over every department of human conduct,
or by the spirit of Puritanism. And some of those modern reformers
who have placed themselves in strongest opposition to the religions
of the past, have been noway behind either churches or sects in
their assertion of the right of spiritual domination: M. Comte,
in particular, whose social system, as unfolded in his Traite
de Politique Positive, aims at establishing (though by moral more
than by legal appliances) a despotism of society over the individual,
surpassing anything contemplated in the political ideal of the
most rigid disciplinarian among the ancient philosophers.
Apart from the peculiar tenets of individual thinkers, there is
also in the world at large an increasing inclination to stretch
unduly the powers of society over the individual, both by the
force of opinion and even by that of legislation: and as the tendency
of all the changes taking place in the world is to strengthen
society, and diminish the power of the individual, this encroachment
is not one of the evils which tend spontaneously to disappear,
but, on the contrary, to grow more and more formidable. The disposition
of mankind, whether as rulers or as fellow-citizens, to impose
their own opinions and inclinations as a rule of conduct on others,
is so energetically supported by some of the best and by some
of the worst feelings incident to human nature, that it is hardly
ever kept under restraint by anything but want of power; and as
the power is not declining, but growing, unless a strong barrier
of moral conviction can be raised against the mischief, we must
expect, in the present circumstances of the world, to see it increase.
It will be convenient for the argument, if, instead of at once
entering upon the general thesis, we confine ourselves in the
first instance to a single branch of it, on which the principle
here stated is, if not fully, yet to a certain point, recognized
by the current opinions. This one branch is the Liberty of Thought:
from which it is impossible to separate the cognate liberty of
speaking and of writing. Although these liberties, to some considerable
amount, form part of the political morality of all countries which
profess religious toleration and free institutions, the grounds,
both philosophical and practical, on which they rest, are perhaps
not so familiar to the general mind, nor so thoroughly appreciated
by many even of the leaders of opinion, as might have been expected.
Those grounds, when rightly understood, are of much wider application
than to only one division of the subject, and a thorough consideration
of this part of the question will be found the best introduction
to the remainder. Those to whom nothing which I am about to say
will be new, may therefore, I hope, excuse me, if on a subject
which for now three centuries has been so often discussed, I venture
on one discussion more.
CHAPTER II OF THE LIBERTY OF THOUGHT AND DISCUSSION
THE time, it is to be hoped, is gone by when any defence would
be necessary of the "liberty of the press" as one of
the securities against corrupt or tyrannical government. No argument,
we may suppose, can now be needed, against permitting a legislature
or an executive, not identified in interest with the people, to
prescribe opinions to them, and determine what doctrines or what
arguments they shall be allowed to hear. This aspect of the question,
besides, has been so often and so triumphantly enforced by preceding
writers, that it needs not be specially insisted on in this place.
Though the law of England, on the subject of the press, is as
servile to this day as it was in the time of the Tudors, there
is little danger of its being actually put in force against political
discussion, except during some temporary panic, when fear of insurrection
drives ministers and judges from their propriety;[1] and, speaking
generally, it is not, in constitutional countries, to be apprehended
that the government, whether completely responsible to the people
or not, will often attempt to control the expression of opinion,
except when in doing so it makes itself the organ of the general
intolerance of the public. Let us suppose, therefore, that the
government is entirely at one with the people, and never thinks
of exerting any power of coercion unless in agreement with what
it conceives to be their voice. But I deny the right of the people
to exercise such coercion, either by themselves or by their government.
The power itself is illegitimate. The best government has no more
title to it than the worst. It is as noxious, or more noxious,
when exerted in accordance with public opinion, than when in opposition
to it. If all mankind minus one, were of one opinion, and only
one person were of the contrary opinion, mankind would be no more
justified in silencing that one person, than he, if he had the
power, would be justified in silencing mankind. Were an opinion
a personal possession of no value except to the owner; if to be
obstructed in the enjoyment of it were simply a private injury,
it would make some difference whether the injury was inflicted
only on a few persons or on many. But the peculiar evil of silencing
the expression of an opinion is, that it is robbing the human
race; posterity as well as the existing generation; those who
dissent from the opinion, still more than those who hold it. If
the opinion is right, they are deprived of the opportunity of
exchanging error for truth: if wrong, they lose, what is almost
as great a benefit, the clearer perception and livelier impression
of truth, produced by its collision with error.
It is necessary to consider separately these two hypotheses, each
of which has a distinct branch of the argument corresponding to
it. We can never be sure that the opinion we are endeavouring
to stifle is a false opinion; and if we were sure, stifling it
would be an evil still.
First: the opinion which it is attempted to suppress by authority
may possibly be true. Those who desire to suppress it, of course
deny its truth; but they are not infallible. They have no authority
to decide the question for all mankind, and exclude every other
person from the means of judging. To refuse a hearing to an opinion,
because they are sure that it is false, is to assume that their
certainty is the same thing as absolute certainty. All silencing
of discussion is an assumption of infallibility. Its condemnation
may be allowed to rest on this common argument, not the worse
for being common.
Unfortunately for the good sense of mankind, the fact of their
fallibility is far from carrying the weight in their practical
judgment, which is always allowed to it in theory; for while every
one well knows himself to be fallible, few think it necessary
to take any precautions against their own fallibility, or admit
the supposition that any opinion of which they feel very certain,
may be one of the examples of the error to which they acknowledge
themselves to be liable. Absolute princes, or others who are accustomed
to unlimited deference, usually feel this complete confidence
in their own opinions on nearly all subjects. People more happily
situated, who sometimes hear their opinions disputed, and are
not wholly unused to be set right when they are wrong, place the
same unbounded reliance only on such of their opinions as are
shared by all who surround them, or to whom they habitually defer:
for in proportion to a man's want of confidence in his own solitary
judgment, does he usually repose, with implicit trust, on the
infallibility of "the world" in general. And the world,
to each individual, means the part of it with which he comes in
contact; his party, his sect, his church, his class of society:
the man may be called, by comparison, almost liberal and largeminded
to whom it means anything so comprehensive as his own country
or his own age. Nor is his faith in this collective authority
at all shaken by his being aware that other ages, countries, sects,
churches, classes, and parties have thought, and even now think,
the exact reverse. He devolves upon his own world the responsibility
of being in the right against the dissentient worlds of other
people; and it never troubles him that mere accident has decided
which of these numerous worlds is the object of his reliance,
and that the same causes which make him a Churchman in London,
would have made him a Buddhist or a Confucian in Pekin. Yet it
is as evident in itself as any amount of argument can make it,
that ages are no more infallible than individuals; every age having
held many opinions which subsequent ages have deemed not only
false but absurd; and it is as certain that many opinions, now
general, will be rejected by future ages, as it is that many,
once general, are rejected by the present.
The objection likely to be made to this argument, would probably
take some such form as the following. There is no greater assumption
of infallibility in forbidding the propagation of error, than
in any other thing which is done by public authority on its own
judgment and responsibility. Judgment is given to men that they
may use it. Because it may be used erroneously, are men to be
told that they ought not to use it at all? To prohibit what they
think pernicious, is not claiming exemption from error, but fulfilling
the duty incumbent on them, although fallible, of acting on their
conscientious conviction. If we were never to act on our opinions,
because those opinions may be wrong, we should leave all our interests
uncared for, and all our duties unperformed. An objection which
applies to all conduct can be no valid objection to any conduct
in particular.
It is the duty of governments, and of individuals, to form the
truest opinions they can; to form them carefully, and never impose
them upon others unless they are quite sure of being right. But
when they are sure (such reasoners may say), it is not conscientiousness
but cowardice to shrink from acting on their opinions, and allow
doctrines which they honestly think dangerous to the welfare of
mankind, either in this life or in another, to be scattered abroad
without restraint, because other people, in less enlightened times,
have persecuted opinions now believed to be true. Let us take
care, it may be said, not to make the same mistake: but governments
and nations have made mistakes in other things, which are not
denied to be fit subjects for the exercise of authority: they
have laid on bad taxes, made unjust wars. Ought we therefore to
lay on no taxes, and, under whatever provocation, make no wars?
Men, and governments, must act to the best of their ability. There
is no such thing as absolute certainty, but there is assurance
sufficient for the purposes of human life. We may, and must, assume
our opinion to be true for the guidance of our own conduct: and
it is assuming no more when we forbid bad men to pervert society
by the propagation of opinions which we regard as false and pernicious.
I answer, that it is assuming very much more. There is the greatest
difference between presuming an opinion to be true, because, with
every opportunity for contesting it, it has not been refuted,
and assuming its truth for the purpose of not permitting its refutation.
Complete liberty of contradicting and disproving our opinion,
is the very condition which justifies us in assuming its truth
for purposes of action; and on no other terms can a being with
human faculties have any rational assurance of being right.
When we consider either the history of opinion, or the ordinary
conduct of human life, to what is it to be ascribed that the one
and the other are no worse than they are? Not certainly to the
inherent force of the human understanding; for, on any matter
not self-evident, there are ninety-nine persons totally incapable
of judging of it, for one who is capable; and the capacity of
the hundredth person is only comparative; for the majority of
the eminent men of every past generation held many opinions now
known to be erroneous, and did or approved numerous things which
no one will now justify. Why is it, then, that there is on the
whole a preponderance among mankind of rational opinions and rational
conduct? If there really is this preponderance--which there must
be, unless human affairs are, and have always been, in an almost
desperate state--it is owing to a quality of the human mind, the
source of everything respectable in man, either as an intellectual
or as a moral being, namely, that his errors are corrigible. He
is capable of rectifying his mistakes by discussion and experience.
Not by experience alone. There must be discussion, to show how
experience is to be interpreted. Wrong opinions and practices
gradually yield to fact and argument: but facts and arguments,
to produce any effect on the mind, must be brought before it.
Very few facts are able to tell their own story, without comments
to bring out their meaning. The whole strength and value, then,
of human judgment, depending on the one property, that it can
be set right when it is wrong, reliance can be placed on it only
when the means of setting it right are kept constantly at hand.
In the case of any person whose judgment is really deserving of
confidence, how has it become so? Because he has kept his mind
open to criticism of his opinions and conduct. Because it has
been his practice to listen to all that could be said against
him; to profit by as much of it as was just, and expound to himself,
and upon occasion to others, the fallacy of what was fallacious.
Because he has felt, that the only way in which a human being
can make some approach to knowing the whole of a subject, is by
hearing what can be said about it by persons of every variety
of opinion, and studying all modes in which it can be looked at
by every character of mind. No wise man ever acquired his wisdom
in any mode but this; nor is it in the nature of human intellect
to become wise in any other manner. The steady habit of correcting
and completing his own opinion by collating it with those of others,
so far from causing doubt and hesitation in carrying it into practice,
is the only stable foundation for a just reliance on it: for,
being cognizant of all that can, at least obviously, be said against
him, and having taken up his position against all gainsayers knowing
that he has sought for objections and difficulties, instead of
avoiding them, and has shut out no light which can be thrown upon
the subject from any quarter--he has a right to think his judgment
better than that of any person, or any multitude, who have not
gone through a similar process.
It is not too much to require that what the wisest of mankind,
those who are best entitled to trust their own judgment, find
necessary to warrant their relying on it, should be submitted
to by that miscellaneous collection of a few wise and many foolish
individuals, called the public. The most intolerant of churches,
the Roman Catholic Church, even at the canonization of a saint,
admits, and listens patiently to, a "devil's advocate."
The holiest of men, it appears, cannot be admitted to posthumous
honors, until all that the devil could say against him is known
and weighed. If even the Newtonian philosophy were not permitted
to be questioned, mankind could not feel as complete assurance
of its truth as they now do. The beliefs which we have most warrant
for, have no safeguard to rest on, but a standing invitation to
the whole world to prove them unfounded. If the challenge is not
accepted, or is accepted and the attempt fails, we are far enough
from certainty still; but we have done the best that the existing
state of human reason admits of; we have neglected nothing that
could give the truth a chance of reaching us: if the lists are
kept open, we may hope that if there be a better truth, it will
be found when the human mind is capable of receiving it; and in
the meantime we may rely on having attained such approach to truth,
as is possible in our own day. This is the amount of certainty
attainable by a fallible being, and this the sole way of attaining
it.
Strange it is, that men should admit the validity of the arguments
for free discussion, but object to their being "pushed to
an extreme;" not seeing that unless the reasons are good
for an extreme case, they are not good for any case. Strange that
they should imagine that they are not assuming infallibility when
they acknowledge that there should be free discussion on all subjects
which can possibly be doubtful, but think that some particular
principle or doctrine should be forbidden to be questioned because
it is so certain, that is, because they are certain that it is
certain. To call any proposition certain, while there is any one
who would deny its certainty if permitted, but who is not permitted,
is to assume that we ourselves, and those who agree with us, are
the judges of certainty, and judges without hearing the other
side.
In the present age--which has been described as "destitute
of faith, but terrified at scepticism,"--in which people
feel sure, not so much that their opinions are true, as that they
should not know what to do without them--the claims of an opinion
to be protected from public attack are rested not so much on its
truth, as on its importance to society. There are, it is alleged,
certain beliefs, so useful, not to say indispensable to well-being,
that it is as much the duty of governments to uphold those beliefs,
as to protect any other of the interests of society. In a case
of such necessity, and so directly in the line of their duty,
something less than infallibility may, it is maintained, warrant,
and even bind, governments, to act on their own opinion, confirmed
by the general opinion of mankind. It is also often argued, and
still oftener thought, that none but bad men would desire to weaken
these salutary beliefs; and there can be nothing wrong, it is
thought, in restraining bad men, and prohibiting what only such
men would wish to practise. This mode of thinking makes the justification
of restraints on discussion not a question of the truth of doctrines,
but of their usefulness; and flatters itself by that means to
escape the responsibility of claiming to be an infallible judge
of opinions. But those who thus satisfy themselves, do not perceive
that the assumption of infallibility is merely shifted from one
point to another. The usefulness of an opinion is itself matter
of opinion: as disputable, as open to discussion and requiring
discussion as much, as the opinion itself. There is the same need
of an infallible judge of opinions to decide an opinion to be
noxious, as to decide it to be false, unless the opinion condemned
has full opportunity of defending itself. And it will not do to
say that the heretic may be allowed to maintain the utility or
harmlessness of his opinion, though forbidden to maintain its
truth. The truth of an opinion is part of its utility. If we would
know whether or not it is desirable that a proposition should
be believed, is it possible to exclude the consideration of whether
or not it is true? In the opinion, not of bad men, but of the
best men, no belief which is contrary to truth can be really useful:
and can you prevent such men from urging that plea, when they
are charged with culpability for denying some doctrine which they
are told is useful, but which they believe to be false? Those
who are on the side of received opinions, never fail to take all
possible advantage of this plea; you do not find them handling
the question of utility as if it could be completely abstracted
from that of truth: on the contrary, it is, above all, because
their doctrine is "the truth," that the knowledge or
the belief of it is held to be so indispensable. There can be
no fair discussion of the question of usefulness, when an argument
so vital may be employed on one side, but not on the other. And
in point of fact, when law or public feeling do not permit the
truth of an opinion to be disputed, they are just as little tolerant
of a denial of its usefulness. The utmost they allow is an extenuation
of its absolute necessity or of the positive guilt of rejecting
it.
In order more fully to illustrate the mischief of denying a hearing
to opinions because we, in our own judgment, have condemned them,
it will be desirable to fix down the discussion to a concrete
case; and I choose, by preference, the cases which are least favourable
to me--in which the argument against freedom of opinion, both
on the score of truth and on that of utility, is considered the
strongest. Let the opinions impugned be the belief in a God and
in a future state, or any of the commonly received doctrines of
morality. To fight the battle on such ground, gives a great advantage
to an unfair antagonist; since he will be sure to say (and many
who have no desire to be unfair will say it internally), Are these
the doctrines which you do not deem sufficiently certain to be
taken under the protection of law? Is the belief in a God one
of the opinions, to feel sure of which, you hold to be assuming
infallibility? But I must be permitted to observe, that it is
not the feeling sure of a doctrine (be it what it may) which I
call an assumption of infallibility. It is the undertaking to
decide that question for others, without allowing them to hear
what can be said on the contrary side. And I denounce and reprobate
this pretension not the less, if put forth on the side of my most
solemn convictions. However positive any one's persuasion may
be, not only of the falsity, but of the pernicious consequences--not
only of the pernicious consequences, but (to adopt expressions
which I altogether condemn) the immorality and impiety of an opinion;
yet if, in pursuance of that private judgment, though backed by
the public judgment of his country or his cotemporaries, he prevents
the opinion from being heard in its defence, he assumes infallibility.
And so far from the assumption being less objectionable or less
dangerous because the opinion is called immoral or impious, this
is the case of all others in which it is most fatal. These are
exactly the occasions on which the men of one generation commit
those dreadful mistakes which excite the astonishment and horror
of posterity. It is among such that we find the instances memorable
in history, when the arm of the law has been employed to root
out the best men and the noblest doctrines; with deplorable success
as to the men, though some of the doctrines have survived to be
(as if in mockery) invoked, in defence of similar conduct towards
those who dissent from them, or from their received interpretation.
Mankind can hardly be too often reminded, that there was once
a man named Socrates, between whom and the legal authorities and
public opinion of his time, there took place a memorable collision.
Born in an age and country abounding in individual greatness,
this man has been handed down to us by those who best knew both
him and the age, as the most virtuous man in it; while we know
him as the head and prototype of all subsequent teachers of virtue,
the source equally of the lofty inspiration of Plato and the judicious
utilitarianism of Aristotle, "i maestri di color che sanno,"
the two headsprings of ethical as of all other philosophy. This
acknowledged master of all the eminent thinkers who have since
lived--whose fame, still growing after more than two thousand
years, all but outweighs the whole remainder of the names which
make his native city illustrious --was put to death by his countrymen,
after a judicial conviction, for impiety and immorality. Impiety,
in denying the gods recognized by the State; indeed his accuser
asserted (see the "Apologia") that he believed in no
gods at all. Immorality, in being, by his doctrines and instructions,
a "corrupter of youth." Of these charges the tribunal,
there is every ground for believing, honestly found him guilty,
and condemned the man who probably of all then born had deserved
best of mankind, to be put to death as a criminal.
To pass from this to the only other instance of judicial iniquity,
the mention of which, after the condemnation of Socrates, would
not be an anti-climax: the event which took place on Calvary rather
more than eighteen hundred years ago. The man who left on the
memory of those who witnessed his life and conversation, such
an impression of his moral grandeur, that eighteen subsequent
centuries have done homage to him as the Almighty in person, was
ignominiously put to death, as what? As a blasphemer. Men did
not merely mistake their benefactor; they mistook him for the
exact contrary of what he was, and treated him as that prodigy
of impiety, which they themselves are now held to be, for their
treatment of him. The feelings with which mankind now regard these
lamentable transactions, especially the latter of the two, render
them extremely unjust in their judgment of the unhappy actors.
These were, to all appearance, not bad men--not worse than men
most commonly are, but rather the contrary; men who possessed
in a full, or somewhat more than a full measure, the religious,
moral, and patriotic feelings of their time and people: the very
kind of men who, in all times, our own included, have every chance
of passing through life blameless and respected. The high-priest
who rent his garments when the words were pronounced, which, according
to all the ideas of his country, constituted the blackest guilt,
was in all probability quite as sincere in his horror and indignation,
as the generality of respectable and pious men now are in the
religious and moral sentiments they profess; and most of those
who now shudder at his conduct, if they had lived in his time
and been born Jews, would have acted precisely as he did. Orthodox
Christians who are tempted to think that those who stoned to death
the first martyrs must have been worse men than they themselves
are, ought to remember that one of those persecutors was Saint
Paul.
Let us add one more example, the most striking of all, if the
impressiveness of an error is measured by the wisdom and virtue
of him who falls into it. If ever any one, possessed of power,
had grounds for thinking himself the best and most enlightened
among his cotemporaries, it was the Emperor Marcus Aurelius. Absolute
monarch of the whole civilized world, he preserved through life
not only the most unblemished justice, but what was less to be
expected from his Stoical breeding, the tenderest heart. The few
failings which are attributed to him, were all on the side of
indulgence: while his writings, the highest ethical product of
the ancient mind, differ scarcely perceptibly, if they differ
at all, from the most characteristic teachings of Christ. This
man, a better Christian in all but the dogmatic sense of the word,
than almost any of the ostensibly Christian sovereigns who have
since reigned, persecuted Christianity. Placed at the summit of
all the previous attainments of humanity, with an open, unfettered
intellect, and a character which led him of himself to embody
in his moral writings the Christian ideal, he yet failed to see
that Christianity was to be a good and not an evil to the world,
with his duties to which he was so deeply penetrated. Existing
society he knew to be in a deplorable state. But such as it was,
he saw or thought he saw, that it was held together and prevented
from being worse, by belief and reverence of the received divinities.
As a ruler of mankind, he deemed it his duty not to suffer society
to fall in pieces; and saw not how, if its existing ties were
removed, any others could be formed which could again knit it
together. The new religion openly aimed at dissolving these ties:
unless, therefore, it was his duty to adopt that religion, it
seemed to be his duty to put it down. Inasmuch then as the theology
of Christianity did not appear to him true or of divine origin;
inasmuch as this strange history of a crucified God was not credible
to him, and a system which purported to rest entirely upon a foundation
to him so wholly unbelievable, could not be foreseen by him to
be that renovating agency which, after all abatements, it has
in fact proved to be; the gentlest and most amiable of philosophers
and rulers, under a solemn sense of duty, authorized the persecution
of Christianity. To my mind this is one of the most tragical facts
in all history. It is a bitter thought, how different a thing
the Christianity of the world might have been, if the Christian
faith had been adopted as the religion of the empire under the
auspices of Marcus Aurelius instead of those of Constantine. But
it would be equally unjust to him and false to truth, to deny,
that no one plea which can be urged for punishing anti-Christian
teaching, was wanting to Marcus Aurelius for punishing, as he
did, the propagation of Christianity. No Christian more firmly
believes that Atheism is false, and tends to the dissolution of
society, than Marcus Aurelius believed the same things of Christianity;
he who, of all men then living, might have been thought the most
capable of appreciating it. Unless any one who approves of punishment
for the promulgation of opinions, flatters himself that he is
a wiser and better man than Marcus Aurelius--more deeply versed
in the wisdom of his time, more elevated in his intellect above
it--more earnest in his search for truth, or more single-minded
in his devotion to it when found;--let him abstain from that assumption
of the joint infallibility of himself and the multitude, which
the great Antoninus made with so unfortunate a result.
Aware of the impossibility of defending the use of punishment
for restraining irreligious opinions, by any argument which will
not justify Marcus Antoninus, the enemies of religious freedom,
when hard pressed, occasionally accept this consequence, and say,
with Dr. Johnson, that the persecutors of Christianity were in
the right; that persecution is an ordeal through which truth ought
to pass, and always passes successfully, legal penalties being,
in the end, powerless against truth, though sometimes beneficially
effective against mischievous errors. This is a form of the argument
for religious intolerance, sufficiently remarkable not to be passed
without notice.
A theory which maintains that truth may justifiably be persecuted
because persecution cannot possibly do it any harm, cannot be
charged with being intentionally hostile to the reception of new
truths; but we cannot commend the generosity of its dealing with
the persons to whom mankind are indebted for them. To discover
to the world something which deeply concerns it, and of which
it was previously ignorant; to prove to it that it had been mistaken
on some vital point of temporal or spiritual interest, is as important
a service as a human being can render to his fellow-creatures,
and in certain cases, as in those of the early Christians and
of the Reformers, those who think with Dr. Johnson believe it
to have been the most precious gift which could be bestowed on
mankind. That the authors of such splendid benefits should be
requited by martyrdom; that their reward should be to be dealt
with as the vilest of criminals, is not, upon this theory, a deplorable
error and misfortune, for which humanity should mourn in sackcloth
and ashes, but the normal and justifiable state of things. The
propounder of a new truth, according to this doctrine, should
stand, as stood, in the legislation of the Locrians, the proposer
of a new law, with a halter round his neck, to be instantly tightened
if the public assembly did not, on hearing his reasons, then and
there adopt his proposition. People who defend this mode of treating
benefactors, can not be supposed to set much value on the benefit;
and I believe this view of the subject is mostly confined to the
sort of persons who think that new truths may have been desirable
once, but that we have had enough of them now.
But, indeed, the dictum that truth always triumphs over persecution,
is one of those pleasant falsehoods which men repeat after one
another till they pass into commonplaces, but which all experience
refutes. History teems with instances of truth put down by persecution.
If not suppressed forever, it may be thrown back for centuries.
To speak only of religious opinions: the Reformation broke out
at least twenty times before Luther, and was put down. Arnold
of Brescia was put down. Fra Dolcino was put down. Savonarola
was put down. The Albigeois were put down. The Vaudois were put
down. The Lollards were put down. The Hussites were put down.
Even after the era of Luther, wherever persecution was persisted
in, it was successful. In Spain, Italy, Flanders, the Austrian
empire, Protestantism was rooted out; and, most likely, would
have been so in England, had Queen Mary lived, or Queen Elizabeth
died. Persecution has always succeeded, save where the heretics
were too strong a party to be effectually persecuted. No reasonable
person can doubt that Christianity might have been extirpated
in the Roman empire. It spread, and became predominant, because
the persecutions were only occasional, lasting but a short time,
and separated by long intervals of almost undisturbed propagandism.
It is a piece of idle sentimentality that truth, merely as truth,
has any inherent power denied to error, of prevailing against
the dungeon and the stake. Men are not more zealous for truth
than they often are for error, and a sufficient application of
legal or even of social penalties will generally succeed in stopping
the propagation of either. The real advantage which truth has,
consists in this, that when an opinion is true, it may be extinguished
once, twice, or many times, but in the course of ages there will
generally be found persons to rediscover it, until some one of
its reappearances falls on a time when from favourable circumstances
it escapes persecution until it has made such head as to withstand
all subsequent attempts to suppress it.
It will be said, that we do not now put to death the introducers
of new opinions: we are not like our fathers who slew the prophets,
we even build sepulchres to them. It is true we no longer put
heretics to death; and the amount of penal infliction which modern
feeling would probably tolerate, even against the most obnoxious
opinions, is not sufficient to extirpate them. But let us not
flatter ourselves that we are yet free from the stain even of
legal persecution. Penalties for opinion, or at least for its
expression, still exist by law; and their enforcement is not,
even in these times, so unexampled as to make it at all incredible
that they may some day be revived in full force. In the year 1857,
at the summer assizes of the county of Cornwall, an unfortunate
man,[2] said to be of unexceptionable conduct in all relations
of life, was sentenced to twenty-one months imprisonment, for
uttering, and writing on a gate, some offensive words concerning
Christianity. Within a month of the same time, at the Old Bailey,
two persons, on two separate occasions,[3] were rejected as jurymen,
and one of them grossly insulted by the judge and one of the counsel,
because they honestly declared that they had no theological belief;
and a third, a foreigner,[4] for the same reason, was denied justice
against a thief. This refusal of redress took place in virtue
of the legal doctrine, that no person can be allowed to give evidence
in a court of justice, who does not profess belief in a God (any
god is sufficient) and in a future state; which is equivalent
to declaring such persons to be outlaws, excluded from the protection
of the tribunals; who may not only be robbed or assaulted with
impunity, if no one but themselves, or persons of similar opinions,
be present, but any one else may be robbed or assaulted with impunity,
if the proof of the fact depends on their evidence. The assumption
on which this is grounded, is that the oath is worthless, of a
person who does not believe in a future state; a proposition which
betokens much ignorance of history in those who assent to it (since
it is historically true that a large proportion of infidels in
all ages have been persons of distinguished integrity and honor);
and would be maintained by no one who had the smallest conception
how many of the persons in greatest repute with the world, both
for virtues and for attainments, are well known, at least to their
intimates, to be unbelievers. The rule, besides, is suicidal,
and cuts away its own foundation. Under pretence that atheists
must be liars, it admits the testimony of all atheists who are
willing to lie, and rejects only those who brave the obloquy of
publicly confessing a detested creed rather than affirm a falsehood.
A rule thus self-convicted of absurdity so far as regards its
professed purpose, can be kept in force only as a badge of hatred,
a relic of persecution; a persecution, too, having the peculiarity
that the qualification for undergoing it is the being clearly
proved not to deserve it. The rule, and the theory it implies,
are hardly less insulting to believers than to infidels. For if
he who does not believe in a future state necessarily lies, it
follows that they who do believe are only prevented from lying,
if prevented they are, by the fear of hell. We will not do the
authors and abettors of the rule the injury of supposing, that
the conception which they have formed of Christian virtue is drawn
from their own consciousness.
These, indeed, are but rags and remnants of persecution, and may
be thought to be not so much an indication of the wish to persecute,
as an example of that very frequent infirmity of English minds,
which makes them take a preposterous pleasure in the assertion
of a bad principle, when they are no longer bad enough to desire
to carry it really into practice. But unhappily there is no security
in the state of the public mind, that the suspension of worse
forms of legal persecution, which has lasted for about the space
of a generation, will continue. In this age the quiet surface
of routine is as often ruffled by attempts to resuscitate past
evils, as to introduce new benefits. What is boasted of at the
present time as the revival of religion, is always, in narrow
and uncultivated minds, at least as much the revival of bigotry;
and where there is the strongest permanent leaven of intolerance
in the feelings of a people, which at all times abides in the
middle classes of this country, it needs but little to provoke
them into actively persecuting those whom they have never ceased
to think proper objects of persecution.[5] For it is this--it
is the opinions men entertain, and the feelings they cherish,
respecting those who disown the beliefs they deem important, which
makes this country not a place of mental freedom. For a long time
past, the chief mischief of the legal penalties is that they strengthen
the social stigma. It is that stigma which is really effective,
and so effective is it, that the profession of opinions which
are under the ban of society is much less common in England, than
is, in many other countries, the avowal of those which incur risk
of judicial punishment. In respect to all persons but those whose
pecuniary circumstances make them independent of the good will
of other people, opinion, on this subject, is as efficacious as
law; men might as well be imprisoned, as excluded from the means
of earning their bread. Those whose bread is already secured,
and who desire no favors from men in power, or from bodies of
men, or from the public, have nothing to fear from the open avowal
of any opinions, but to be ill-thought of and illspoken of, and
this it ought not to require a very heroic mould to enable them
to bear. There is no room for any appeal ad misericordiam in behalf
of such persons. But though we do not now inflict so much evil
on those who think differently from us, as it was formerly our
custom to do, it may be that we do ourselves as much evil as ever
by our treatment of them. Socrates was put to death, but the Socratic
philosophy rose like the sun in heaven, and spread its illumination
over the whole intellectual firmament. Christians were cast to
the lions, but the Christian Church grew up a stately and spreading
tree, overtopping the older and less vigorous growths, and stifling
them by its shade. Our merely social intolerance, kills no one,
roots out no opinions, but induces men to disguise them, or to
abstain from any active effort for their diffusion. With us, heretical
opinions do not perceptibly gain or even lose, ground in each
decade or generation; they never blaze out far and wide, but continue
to smoulder in the narrow circles of thinking and studious persons
among whom they originate, without ever lighting up the general
affairs of mankind with either a true or a deceptive light. And
thus is kept up a state of things very satisfactory to some minds,
because, without the unpleasant process of fining or imprisoning
anybody, it maintains all prevailing opinions outwardly undisturbed,
while it does not absolutely interdict the exercise of reason
by dissentients afflicted with the malady of thought. A convenient
plan for having peace in the intellectual world, and keeping all
things going on therein very much as they do already. But the
price paid for this sort of intellectual pacification, is the
sacrifice of the entire moral courage of the human mind. A state
of things in which a large portion of the most active and inquiring
intellects find it advisable to keep the genuine principles and grounds of their convictions within their own breasts, and attempt,
in what they address to the public, to fit as much as they can
of their own conclusions to premises which they have internally
renounced, cannot send forth the open, fearless characters, and
logical, consistent intellects who once adorned the thinking world.
The sort of men who can be looked for under it, are either mere
conformers to commonplace, or time-servers for truth whose arguments
on all great subjects are meant for their hearers, and are not
those which have convinced themselves. Those who avoid this alternative,
do so by narrowing their thoughts and interests to things which
can be spoken of without venturing within the region of principles,
that is, to small practical matters, which would come right of
themselves, if but the minds of mankind were strengthened and
enlarged, and which will never be made effectually right until
then; while that which would strengthen and enlarge men's minds,
free and daring speculation on the highest subjects, is abandoned.
Those in whose eyes this reticence on the part of heretics is
no evil, should consider in the first place, that in consequence
of it there is never any fair and thorough discussion of heretical
opinions; and that such of them as could not stand such a discussion,
though they may be prevented from spreading, do not disappear.
But it is not the minds of heretics that are deteriorated most,
by the ban placed on all inquiry which does not end in the orthodox
conclusions. The greatest harm done is to those who are not heretics,
and whose whole mental development is cramped, and their reason
cowed, by the fear of heresy. Who can compute what the world loses
in the multitude of promising intellects combined with timid characters,
who dare not follow out any bold, vigorous, independent train
of thought, lest it should land them in something which would
admit of being considered irreligious or immoral? Among them we
may occasionally see some man of deep conscientiousness, and subtile
and refined understanding, who spends a life in sophisticating
with an intellect which he cannot silence, and exhausts the resources
of ingenuity in attempting to reconcile the promptings of his
conscience and reason with orthodoxy, which yet he does not, perhaps,
to the end succeed in doing. No one can be a great thinker who
does not recognize, that as a thinker it is his first duty to
follow his intellect to whatever conclusions it may lead. Truth
gains more even by the errors of one who, with due study and preparation,
thinks for himself, than by the true opinions of those who only
hold them because they do not suffer themselves to think. Not
that it is solely, or chiefly, to form great thinkers, that freedom
of thinking is required. On the contrary, it is as much, and even
more indispensable, to enable average human beings to attain the
mental stature which they are capable of. There have been, and
may again be, great individual thinkers, in a general atmosphere
of mental slavery. But there never has been, nor ever will be,
in that atmosphere, an intellectually active people. Where any
people has made a temporary approach to such a character, it has
been because the dread of heterodox speculation was for a time
suspended. Where there is a tacit convention that principles are
not to be disputed; where the discussion of the greatest questions
which can occupy humanity is considered to be closed, we cannot
hope to find that generally high scale of mental activity which
has made some periods of history so remarkable. Never when controversy
avoided the subjects which are large and important enough to kindle
enthusiasm, was the mind of a people stirred up from its foundations,
and the impulse given which raised even persons of the most ordinary
intellect to something of the dignity of thinking beings. Of such
we have had an example in the condition of Europe during the times
immediately following the Reformation; another, though limited
to the Continent and to a more cultivated class, in the speculative
movement of the latter half of the eighteenth century; and a third,
of still briefer duration, in the intellectual fermentation of
Germany during the Goethian and Fichtean period. These periods
differed widely in the particular opinions which they developed;
but were alike in this, that during all three the yoke of authority
was broken. In each, an old mental despotism had been thrown off,
and no new one had yet taken its place. The impulse given at these
three periods has made Europe what it now is. Every single improvement
which has taken place either in the human mind or in institutions,
may be traced distinctly to one or other of them. Appearances
have for some time indicated that all three impulses are well-nigh
spent; and we can expect no fresh start, until we again assert
our mental freedom.
Let us now pass to the second division of the argument, and dismissing
the Supposition that any of the received opinions may be false,
let us assume them to be true, and examine into the worth of the
manner in which they are likely to be held, when their truth is
not freely and openly canvassed. However unwillingly a person
who has a strong opinion may admit the possibility that his opinion
may be false, he ought to be moved by the consideration that however
true it may be, if it is not fully, frequently, and fearlessly
discussed, it will be held as a dead dogma, not a living truth.
There is a class of persons (happily not quite so numerous as
formerly) who think it enough if a person assents undoubtingly
to what they think true, though he has no knowledge whatever of
the grounds of the opinion, and could not make a tenable defence
of it against the most superficial objections. Such persons, if
they can once get their creed taught from authority, naturally
think that no good, and some harm, comes of its being allowed
to be questioned. Where their influence prevails, they make it
nearly impossible for the received opinion to be rejected wisely
and considerately, though it may still be rejected rashly and
ignorantly; for to shut out discussion entirely is seldom possible,
and when it once gets in, beliefs not grounded on conviction are
apt to give way before the slightest semblance of an argument.
Waiving, however, this possibility--assuming that the true opinion
abides in the mind, but abides as a prejudice, a belief independent
of, and proof against, argument--this is not the way in which
truth ought to be held by a rational being. This is not knowing
the truth. Truth, thus held, is but one superstition the more,
accidentally clinging to the words which enunciate a truth.
If the intellect and judgment of mankind ought to be cultivated,
a thing which Protestants at least do not deny, on what can these
faculties be more appropriately exercised by any one, than on
the things which concern him so much that it is considered necessary
for him to hold opinions on them? If the cultivation of the understanding
consists in one thing more than in another, it is surely in learning
the grounds of one's own opinions. Whatever people believe, on
subjects on which it is of the first importance to believe rightly,
they ought to be able to defend against at least the common objections.
But, some one may say, "Let them be taught the grounds of
their opinions. It does not follow that opinions must be merely
parroted because they are never heard controverted. Persons who
learn geometry do not simply commit the theorems to memory, but
understand and learn likewise the demonstrations; and it would
be absurd to say that they remain ignorant of the grounds of geometrical
truths, because they never hear any one deny, and attempt to disprove
them." Undoubtedly: and such teaching suffices on a subject
like mathematics, where there is nothing at all to be said on
the wrong side of the question. The peculiarity of the evidence
of mathematical truths is, that all the argument is on one side.
There are no objections, and no answers to objections. But on
every subject on which difference of opinion is possible, the
truth depends on a balance to be struck between two sets of conflicting
reasons. Even in natural philosophy, there is always some other
explanation possible of the same facts; some geocentric theory
instead of heliocentric, some phlogiston instead of oxygen; and
it has to be shown why that other theory cannot be the true one:
and until this is shown and until we know how it is shown, we
do not understand the grounds of our opinion. But when we turn
to subjects infinitely more complicated, to morals, religion,
politics, social relations, and the business of life, three-fourths
of the arguments for every disputed opinion consist in dispelling
the appearances which favor some opinion different from it. The
greatest orator, save one, of antiquity, has left it on record
that he always studied his adversary's case with as great, if
not with still greater, intensity than even his own. What Cicero
practised as the means of forensic success, requires to be imitated
by all who study any subject in order to arrive at the truth.
He who knows only his own side of the case, knows little of that.
His reasons may be good, and no one may have been able to refute
them. But if he is equally unable to refute the reasons on the
opposite side; if he does not so much as know what they are, he
has no ground for preferring either opinion. The rational position
for him would be suspension of judgment, and unless he contents
himself with that, he is either led by authority, or adopts, like
the generality of the world, the side to which he feels most inclination.
Nor is it enough that he should hear the arguments of adversaries
from his own teachers, presented as they state them, and accompanied
by what they offer as refutations. This is not the way to do justice
to the arguments, or bring them into real contact with his own
mind. He must be able to hear them from persons who actually believe
them; who defend them in earnest, and do their very utmost for
them. He must know them in their most plausible and persuasive
form; he must feel the whole force of the difficulty which the
true view of the subject has to encounter and dispose of, else
he will never really possess himself of the portion of truth which
meets and removes that difficulty. Ninety-nine in a hundred of
what are called educated men are in this condition, even of those
who can argue fluently for their opinions. Their conclusion may
be true, but it might be false for anything they know: they have
never thrown themselves into the mental position of those who
think differently from them, and considered what such persons
may have to say; and consequently they do not, in any proper sense
of the word, know the doctrine which they themselves profess.
They do not know those parts of it which explain and justify the
remainder; the considerations which show that a fact which seemingly
conflicts with another is reconcilable with it, or that, of two
apparently strong reasons, one and not the other ought to be preferred.
All that part of the truth which turns the scale, and decides
the judgment of a completely informed mind, they are strangers
to; nor is it ever really known, but to those who have attended
equally and impartially to both sides, and endeavored to see the
reasons of both in the strongest light. So essential is this discipline
to a real understanding of moral and human subjects, that if opponents
of all important truths do not exist, it is indispensable to imagine
them and supply them with the strongest arguments which the most
skilful devil's advocate can conjure up.
To abate the force of these considerations, an enemy of free discussion
may be supposed to say, that there is no necessity for mankind
in general to know and understand all that can be said against
or for their opinions by philosophers and theologians. That it
is not needful for common men to be able to expose all the misstatements
or fallacies of an ingenious opponent. That it is enough if there
is always somebody capable of answering them, so that nothing
likely to mislead uninstructed persons remains unrefuted. That
simple minds, having been taught the obvious grounds of the truths
inculcated on them, may trust to authority for the rest, and being
aware that they have neither knowledge nor talent to resolve every
difficulty which can be raised, may repose in the assurance that
all those which have been raised have been or can be answered,
by those who are specially trained to the task.
Conceding to this view of the subject the utmost that can be claimed
for it by those most easily satisfied with the amount of understanding
of truth which ought to accompany the belief of it; even so, the
argument for free discussion is no way weakened. For even this
doctrine acknowledges that mankind ought to have a rational assurance
that all objections have been satisfactorily answered; and how
are they to be answered if that which requires to be answered
is not spoken? or how can the answer be known to be satisfactory,
if the objectors have no opportunity of showing that it is unsatisfactory?
If not the public, at least the philosophers and theologians who
are to resolve the difficulties, must make themselves familiar
with those difficulties in their most puzzling form; and this
cannot be accomplished unless they are freely stated, and placed
in the most advantageous light which they admit of. The Catholic
Church has its own way of dealing with this embarrassing problem.
It makes a broad separation between those who can be permitted
to receive its doctrines on conviction, and those who must accept
them on trust. Neither, indeed, are allowed any choice as to what
they will accept; but the clergy, such at least as can be fully
confided in, may admissibly and meritoriously make themselves
acquainted with the arguments of opponents, in order to answer
them, and may, therefore, read heretical books; the laity, not
unless by special permission, hard to be obtained. This discipline
recognizes a knowledge of the enemy's case as beneficial to the
teachers, but finds means, consistent with this, of denying it
to the rest of the world: thus giving to the elite more mental
culture, though not more mental freedom, than it allows to the
mass. By this device it succeeds in obtaining the kind of mental
superiority which its purposes require; for though culture without
freedom never made a large and liberal mind, it can make a clever
nisi prius advocate of a cause. But in countries professing Protestantism,
this resource is denied; since Protestants hold, at least in theory,
that the responsibility for the choice of a religion must be borne
by each for himself, and cannot be thrown off upon teachers. Besides,
in the present state of the world, it is practically impossible
that writings which are read by the instructed can be kept from
the uninstructed. If the teachers of mankind are to be cognizant
of all that they ought to know, everything must be free to be
written and published without restraint.
If, however, the mischievous operation of the absence of free
discussion, when the received opinions are true, were confined
to leaving men ignorant of the grounds of those opinions, it might
be thought that this, if an intellectual, is no moral evil, and
does not affect the worth of the opinions, regarded in their influence
on the character. The fact, however, is, that not only the grounds
of the opinion are forgotten in the absence of discussion, but
too often the meaning of the opinion itself. The words which convey
it, cease to suggest ideas, or suggest only a small portion of
those they were originally employed to communicate. Instead of
a vivid conception and a living belief, there remain only a few
phrases retained by rote; or, if any part, the shell and husk
only of the meaning is retained, the finer essence being lost.
The great chapter in human history which this fact occupies and
fills, cannot be too earnestly studied and meditated on.
It is illustrated in the experience of almost all ethical doctrines
and religious creeds. They are all full of meaning and vitality
to those who originate them, and to the direct disciples of the
originators. Their meaning continues to be felt in undiminished
strength, and is perhaps brought out into even fuller consciousness,
so long as the struggle lasts to give the doctrine or creed an
ascendency over other creeds. At last it either prevails, and
becomes the general opinion, or its progress stops; it keeps possession
of the ground it has gained, but ceases to spread further. When
either of these results has become apparent, controversy on the
subject flags, and gradually dies away. The doctrine has taken
its place, if not as a received opinion, as one of the admitted
sects or divisions of opinion: those who hold it have generally
inherited, not adopted it; and conversion from one of these doctrines
to another, being now an exceptional fact, occupies little place
in the thoughts of their professors. Instead of being, as at first,
constantly on the alert either to defend themselves against the
world, or to bring the world over to them, they have subsided
into acquiescence, and neither listen, when they can help it,
to arguments against their creed, nor trouble dissentients (if
there be such) with arguments in its favor. From this time may
usually be dated the decline in the living power of the doctrine.
We often hear the teachers of all creeds lamenting the difficulty
of keeping up in the minds of believers a lively apprehension
of the truth which they nominally recognize, so that it may penetrate
the feelings, and acquire a real mastery over the conduct. No
such difficulty is complained of while the creed is still fighting
for its existence: even the weaker combatants then know and feel
what they are fighting for, and the difference between it and
other doctrines; and in that period of every creed's existence,
not a few persons may be found, who have realized its fundamental
principles in all the forms of thought, have weighed and considered
them in all their important bearings, and have experienced the
full effect on the character, which belief in that creed ought
to produce in a mind thoroughly imbued with it. But when it has
come to be an hereditary creed, and to be received passively,
not actively--when the mind is no longer compelled, in the same
degree as at first, to exercise its vital powers on the questions
which its belief presents to it, there is a progressive tendency
to forget all of the belief except the formularies, or to give
it a dull and torpid assent, as if accepting it on trust dispensed
with the necessity of realizing it in consciousness, or testing
it by personal experience; until it almost ceases to connect itself
at all with the inner life of the human being. Then are seen the
cases, so frequent in this age of the world as almost to form
the majority, in which the creed remains as it were outside the
mind, encrusting and petrifying it against all other influences
addressed to the higher parts of our nature; manifesting its power
by not suffering any fresh and living conviction to get in, but
itself doing nothing for the mind or heart, except standing sentinel
over them to keep them vacant.
To what an extent doctrines intrinsically fitted to make the deepest
impression upon the mind may remain in it as dead beliefs, without
being ever realized in the imagination, the feelings, or the understanding,
is exemplified by the manner in which the majority of believers
hold the doctrines of Christianity. By Christianity I here mean
what is accounted such by all churches and sects--the maxims and
precepts contained in the New Testament. These are considered
sacred, and accepted as laws, by all professing Christians. Yet
it is scarcely too much to say that not one Christian in a thousand
guides or tests his individual conduct by reference to those laws.
The standard to which he does refer it, is the custom of his nation,
his class, or his religious profession. He has thus, on the one
hand, a collection of ethical maxims, which he believes to have
been vouchsafed to him by infallible wisdom as rules for his government;
and on the other, a set of every-day judgments and practices,
which go a certain length with some of those maxims, not so great
a length with others, stand in direct opposition to some, and
are, on the whole, a compromise between the Christian creed and
the interests and suggestions of worldly life. To the first of
these standards he gives his homage; to the other his real allegiance.
All Christians believe that the blessed are the poor and humble,
and those who are illused by the world; that it is easier for
a camel to pass through the eye of a needle than for a rich man
to enter the kingdom of heaven; that they should judge not, lest
they be judged; that they should swear not at all; that they should
love their neighbor as themselves; that if one take their cloak,
they should give him their coat also; that they should take no
thought for the morrow; that if they would be perfect, they should
sell all that they have and give it to the poor. They are not
insincere when they say that they believe these things. They do
believe them, as people believe what they have always heard lauded
and never discussed. But in the sense of that living belief which
regulates conduct, they believe these doctrines just up to the
point to which it is usual to act upon them. The doctrines in
their integrity are serviceable to pelt adversaries with; and
it is understood that they are to be put forward (when possible)
as the reasons for whatever people do that they think laudable.
But any one who reminded them that the maxims require an infinity
of things which they never even think of doing would gain nothing
but to be classed among those very unpopular characters who affect
to be better than other people. The doctrines have no hold on
ordinary believers--are not a power in their minds. They have
an habitual respect for the sound of them, but no feeling which
spreads from the words to the things signified, and forces the
mind to take them in, and make them conform to the formula. Whenever
conduct is concerned, they look round for Mr. A and B to direct
them how far to go in obeying Christ.
Now we may be well assured that the case was not thus, but far
otherwise, with the early Christians. Had it been thus, Christianity
never would have expanded from an obscure sect of the despised
Hebrews into the religion of the Roman empire. When their enemies
said, "See how these Christians love one another" (a
remark not likely to be made by anybody now), they assuredly had
a much livelier feeling of the meaning of their creed than they
have ever had since. And to this cause, probably, it is chiefly
owing that Christianity now makes so little progress in extending
its domain, and after eighteen centuries, is still nearly confined
to Europeans and the descendants of Europeans. Even with the strictly
religious, who are much in earnest about their doctrines, and
attach a greater amount of meaning to many of them than people
in general, it commonly happens that the part which is thus comparatively
active in their minds is that which was made by Calvin, or Knox,
or some such person much nearer in character to themselves. The
sayings of Christ coexist passively in their minds, producing
hardly any effect beyond what is caused by mere listening to words
so amiable and bland. There are many reasons, doubtless, why doctrines
which are the badge of a sect retain more of their vitality than
those common to all recognized sects, and why more pains are taken
by teachers to keep their meaning alive; but one reason certainly
is, that the peculiar doctrines are more questioned, and have
to be oftener defended against open gainsayers. Both teachers
and learners go to sleep at their post, as soon as there is no
enemy in the field.
The same thing holds true, generally speaking, of all traditional
doctrines--those of prudence and knowledge of life, as well as
of morals or religion. All languages and literatures are full
of general observations on life, both as to what it is, and how
to conduct oneself in it; observations which everybody knows,
which everybody repeats, or hears with acquiescence, which are
received as truisms, yet of which most people first truly learn
the meaning, when experience, generally of a painful kind, has
made it a reality to them. How often, when smarting under some
unforeseen misfortune or disappointment, does a person call to
mind some proverb or common saying familiar to him all his life,
the meaning of which, if he had ever before felt it as he does
now, would have saved him from the calamity. There are indeed
reasons for this, other than the absence of discussion: there
are many truths of which the full meaning cannot be realized,
until personal experience has brought it home. But much more of
the meaning even of these would have been understood, and what
was understood would have been far more deeply impressed on the
mind, if the man had been accustomed to hear it argued pro and
con by people who did understand it. The fatal tendency of mankind
to leave off thinking about a thing when it is no longer doubtful,
is the cause of half their errors. A contemporary author has well
spoken of "the deep slumber of a decided opinion."
But what! (it may be asked) Is the absence of unanimity an indispensable
condition of true knowledge? Is it necessary that some part of
mankind should persist in error, to enable any to realize the
truth? Does a belief cease to be real and vital as soon as it
is generally received--and is a proposition never thoroughly understood
and felt unless some doubt of it remains? As soon as mankind have
unanimously accepted a truth, does the truth perish within them?
The highest aim and best result of improved intelligence, it has
hitherto been thought, is to unite mankind more and more in the
acknowledgment of all important truths: and does the intelligence
only last as long as it has not achieved its object? Do the fruits
of conquest perish by the very completeness of the victory?
I affirm no such thing. As mankind improve, the number of doctrines
which are no longer disputed or doubted will be constantly on
the increase: and the well-being of mankind may almost be measured
by the number and gravity of the truths which have reached the
point of being uncontested. The cessation, on one question after
another, of serious controversy, is one of the necessary incidents
of the consolidation of opinion; a consolidation as salutary in
the case of true opinions, as it is dangerous and noxious when
the opinions are erroneous. But though this gradual narrowing
of the bounds of diversity of opinion is necessary in both senses
of the term, being at once inevitable and indispensable, we are
not therefore obliged to conclude that all its consequences must
be beneficial. The loss of so important an aid to the intelligent
and living apprehension of a truth, as is afforded by the necessity
of explaining it to, or defending it against, opponents, though
not sufficient to outweigh, is no trifling drawback from, the
benefit of its universal recognition. Where this advantage can
no longer be had, I confess I should like to see the teachers
of mankind endeavoring to provide a substitute for it; some contrivance
for making the difficulties of the question as present to the
learner's consciousness, as if they were pressed upon him by a
dissentient champion, eager for his conversion.
But instead of seeking contrivances for this purpose, they have
lost those they formerly had. The Socratic dialectics, so magnificently
exemplified in the dialogues of Plato, were a contrivance of this
description. They were essentially a negative discussion of the
great questions of philosophy and life, directed with consummate
skill to the purpose of convincing any one who had merely adopted
the commonplaces of received opinion, that he did not understand
the subject --that he as yet attached no definite meaning to the
doctrines he professed; in order that, becoming aware of his ignorance,
he might be put in the way to attain a stable belief, resting
on a clear apprehension both of the meaning of doctrines and of
their evidence. The school disputations of the Middle Ages had
a somewhat similar object. They were intended to make sure that
the pupil understood his own opinion, and (by necessary correlation)
the opinion opposed to it, and could enforce the grounds of the
one and confute those of the other. These last-mentioned contests
had indeed the incurable defect, that the premises appealed to
were taken from authority, not from reason; and, as a discipline
to the mind, they were in every respect inferior to the powerful
dialectics which formed the intellects of the "Socratici
viri:" but the modern mind owes far more to both than it
is generally willing to admit, and the present modes of education
contain nothing which in the smallest degree supplies the place
either of the one or of the other. A person who derives all his
instruction from teachers or books, even if he escape the besetting
temptation of contenting himself with cram, is under no compulsion
to hear both sides; accordingly it is far from a frequent accomplishment,
even among thinkers, to know both sides; and the weakest part
of what everybody says in defence of his opinion, is what he intends
as a reply to antagonists. It is the fashion of the present time
to disparage negative logic --that which points out weaknesses
in theory or errors in practice, without establishing positive
truths. Such negative criticism would indeed be poor enough as
an ultimate result; but as a means to attaining any positive knowledge
or conviction worthy the name, it cannot be valued too highly;
and until people are again systematically trained to it, there
will be few great thinkers, and a low general average of intellect,
in any but the mathematical and physical departments of speculation.
On any other subject no one's opinions deserve the name of knowledge,
except so far as he has either had forced upon him by others,
or gone through of himself, the same mental process which would
have been required of him in carrying on an active controversy
with opponents. That, therefore, which when absent, it is so indispensable,
but so difficult, to create, how worse than absurd is it to forego,
when spontaneously offering itself! If there are any persons who
contest a received opinion, or who will do so if law or opinion
will let them, let us thank them for it, open our minds to listen
to them, and rejoice that there is some one to do for us what
we otherwise ought, if we have any regard for either the certainty
or the vitality of our convictions, to do with much greater labor
for ourselves.
It still remains to speak of one of the principal causes which
make diversity of opinion advantageous, and will continue to do
so until mankind shall have entered a stage of intellectual advancement
which at present seems at an incalculable distance. We have hitherto
considered only two possibilities: that the received opinion may
be false, and some other opinion, consequently, true; or that,
the received opinion being true, a conflict with the opposite
error is essential to a clear apprehension and deep feeling of
its truth. But there is a commoner case than either of these;
when the conflicting doctrines, instead of being one true and
the other false, share the truth between them; and the nonconforming
opinion is needed to supply the remainder of the truth, of which
the received doctrine embodies only a part. Popular opinions,
on subjects not palpable to sense, are often true, but seldom
or never the whole truth. They are a part of the truth; sometimes
a greater, sometimes a smaller part, but exaggerated, distorted,
and disjoined from the truths by which they ought to be accompanied
and limited. Heretical opinions, on the other hand, are generally
some of these suppressed and neglected truths, bursting the bonds
which kept them down, and either seeking reconciliation with the
truth contained in the common opinion, or fronting it as enemies,
and setting themselves up, with similar exclusiveness, as the
whole truth. The latter case is hitherto the most frequent, as,
in the human mind, one-sidedness has always been the rule, and
many-sidedness the exception. Hence, even in revolutions of opinion,
one part of the truth usually sets while another rises. Even progress,
which ought to superadd, for the most part only substitutes one
partial and incomplete truth for another; improvement consisting
chiefly in this, that the new fragment of truth is more wanted,
more adapted to the needs of the time, than that which it displaces.
Such being the partial character of prevailing opinions, even
when resting on a true foundation; every opinion which embodies
somewhat of the portion of truth which the common opinion omits,
ought to be considered precious, with whatever amount of error
and confusion that truth may be blended. No sober judge of human
affairs will feel bound to be indignant because those who force
on our notice truths which we should otherwise have overlooked,
overlook some of those which we see. Rather, he will think that
so long as popular truth is one-sided, it is more desirable than
otherwise that unpopular truth should have one-sided asserters
too; such being usually the most energetic, and the most likely
to compel reluctant attention to the fragment of wisdom which
they proclaim as if it were the whole.
Thus, in the eighteenth century, when nearly all the instructed,
and all those of the uninstructed who were led by them, were lost
in admiration of what is called civilization, and of the marvels
of modern science, literature, and philosophy, and while greatly
overrating the amount of unlikeness between the men of modern
and those of ancient times, indulged the belief that the whole
of the difference was in their own favor; with what a salutary
shock did the paradoxes of Rousseau explode like bombshells in
the midst, dislocating the compact mass of one-sided opinion,
and forcing its elements to recombine in a better form and with
additional ingredients. Not that the current opinions were on
the whole farther from the truth than Rousseau's were; on the
contrary, they were nearer to it; they contained more of positive
truth, and very much less of error. Nevertheless there lay in
Rousseau's doctrine, and has floated down the stream of opinion
along with it, a considerable amount of exactly those truths which
the popular opinion wanted; and these are the deposit which was
left behind when the flood subsided. The superior worth of simplicity
of life, the enervating and demoralizing effect of the trammels
and hypocrisies of artificial society, are ideas which have never
been entirely absent from cultivated minds since Rousseau wrote;
and they will in time produce their due effect, though at present
needing to be asserted as much as ever, and to be asserted by
deeds, for words, on this subject, have nearly exhausted their
power.
In politics, again, it is almost a commonplace, that a party of
order or stability, and a party of progress or reform, are both
necessary elements of a healthy state of political life; until
the one or the other shall have so enlarged its mental grasp as
to be a party equally of order and of progress, knowing and distinguishing
what is fit to be preserved from what ought to be swept away.
Each of these modes of thinking derives its utility from the deficiencies
of the other; but it is in a great measure the opposition of the
other that keeps each within the limits of reason and sanity.
Unless opinions favorable to democracy and to aristocracy, to
property and to equality, to co-operation and to competition,
to luxury and to abstinence, to sociality and individuality, to
liberty and discipline, and all the other standing antagonisms
of practical life, are expressed with equal freedom, and enforced
and defended with equal talent and energy, there is no chance
of both elements obtaining their due; one scale is sure to go
up, and the other down. Truth, in the great practical concerns
of life, is so much a question of the reconciling and combining
of opposites, that very few have minds sufficiently capacious
and impartial to make the adjustment with an approach to correctness,
and it has to be made by the rough process of a struggle between
combatants fighting under hostile banners. On any of the great
open questions just enumerated, if either of the two opinions
has a better claim than the other, not merely to be tolerated,
but to be encouraged and countenanced, it is the one which happens
at the particular time and place to be in a minority. That is
the opinion which, for the time being, represents the neglected
interests, the side of human well-being which is in danger of
obtaining less than its share. I am aware that there is not, in
this country, any intolerance of differences of opinion on most
of these topics. They are adduced to show, by admitted and multiplied
examples, the universality of the fact, that only through diversity
of opinion is there, in the existing state of human intellect,
a chance of fair play to all sides of the truth. When there are
persons to be found, who form an exception to the apparent unanimity
of the world on any subject, even if the world is in the right,
it is always probable that dissentients have something worth hearing
to say for themselves, and that truth would lose something by
their silence.
It may be objected, "But some received principles, especially
on the highest and most vital subjects, are more than half-truths.
The Christian morality, for instance, is the whole truth on that
subject and if any one teaches a morality which varies from it,
he is wholly in error." As this is of all cases the most
important in practice, none can be fitter to test the general
maxim. But before pronouncing what Christian morality is or is
not, it would be desirable to decide what is meant by Christian
morality. If it means the morality of the New Testament, I wonder
that any one who derives his knowledge of this from the book itself,
can suppose that it was announced, or intended, as a complete
doctrine of morals. The Gospel always refers to a preexisting
morality, and confines its precepts to the particulars in which
that morality was to be corrected, or superseded by a wider and
higher; expressing itself, moreover, in terms most general, often
impossible to be interpreted literally, and possessing rather
the impressiveness of poetry or eloquence than the precision of
legislation. To extract from it a body of ethical doctrine, has
never been possible without eking it out from the Old Testament,
that is, from a system elaborate indeed, but in many respects
barbarous, and intended only for a barbarous people. St. Paul,
a declared enemy to this Judaical mode of interpreting the doctrine
and filling up the scheme of his Master, equally assumes a preexisting
morality, namely, that of the Greeks and Romans; and his advice
to Christians is in a great measure a system of accommodation
to that; even to the extent of giving an apparent sanction to
slavery. What is called Christian, but should rather be termed
theological, morality, was not the work of Christ or the Apostles,
but is of much later origin, having been gradually built up by
the Catholic Church of the first five centuries, and though not
implicitly adopted by moderns and Protestants, has been much less
modified by them than might have been expected. For the most part,
indeed, they have contented themselves with cutting off the additions
which had been made to it in the Middle Ages, each sect supplying
the place by fresh additions, adapted to its own character and
tendencies. That mankind owe a great debt to this morality, and
to its early teachers, I should be the last person to deny; but
I do not scruple to say of it, that it is, in many important points,
incomplete and one-sided, and that unless ideas and feelings,
not sanctioned by it, had contributed to the formation of European
life and character, human affairs would have been in a worse condition
than they now are. Christian morality (so called) has all the
characters of a reaction; it is, in great part, a protest against
Paganism. Its ideal is negative rather than positive; passive
rather than active; Innocence rather than Nobleness; Abstinence
from Evil, rather than energetic Pursuit of Good: in its precepts
(as has been well said) "thou shalt not" predominates
unduly over "thou shalt." In its horror of sensuality,
it made an idol of asceticism, which has been gradually compromised
away into one of legality. It holds out the hope of heaven and
the threat of hell, as the appointed and appropriate motives to
a virtuous life: in this falling far below the best of the ancients,
and doing what lies in it to give to human morality an essentially
selfish character, by disconnecting each man's feelings of duty
from the interests of his fellow-creatures, except so far as a
self-interested inducement is offered to him for consulting them.
It is essentially a doctrine of passive obedience; it inculcates
submission to all authorities found established; who indeed are
not to be actively obeyed when they command what religion forbids,
but who are not to be resisted, far less rebelled against, for
any amount of wrong to ourselves. And while, in the morality of
the best Pagan nations, duty to the State holds even a disproportionate
place, infringing on the just liberty of the individual; in purely
Christian ethics that grand department of duty is scarcely noticed
or acknowledged. It is in the Koran, not the New Testament, that
we read the maxim--"A ruler who appoints any man to an office,
when there is in his dominions another man better qualified for
it, sins against God and against the State." What little
recognition the idea of obligation to the public obtains in modern
morality, is derived from Greek and Roman sources, not from Christian;
as, even in the morality of private life, whatever exists of magnanimity,
high-mindedness, personal dignity, even the sense of honor, is
derived from the purely human, not the religious part of our education,
and never could have grown out of a standard of ethics in which
the only worth, professedly recognized, is that of obedience.
I am as far as any one from pretending that these defects are
necessarily inherent in the Christian ethics, in every manner
in which it can be conceived, or that the many requisites of a
complete moral doctrine which it does not contain, do not admit
of being reconciled with it. Far less would I insinuate this of
the doctrines and precepts of Christ himself. I believe that the
sayings of Christ are all, that I can see any evidence of their
having been intended to be; that they are irreconcilable with
nothing which a comprehensive morality requires; that everything
which is excellent in ethics may be brought within them, with
no greater violence to their language than has been done to it
by all who have attempted to deduce from them any practical system
of conduct whatever. But it is quite consistent with this, to
believe that they contain and were meant to contain, only a part
of the truth; that many essential elements of the highest morality
are among the things which are not provided for, nor intended
to be provided for, in the recorded deliverances of the Founder
of Christianity, and which have been entirely thrown aside in
the system of ethics erected on the basis of those deliverances
by the Christian Church. And this being so, I think it a great
error to persist in attempting to find in the Christian doctrine
that complete rule for our guidance, which its author intended
it to sanction and enforce, but only partially to provide. I believe,
too, that this narrow theory is becoming a grave practical evil,
detracting greatly from the value of the moral training and instruction,
which so many wellmeaning persons are now at length exerting themselves
to promote. I much fear that by attempting to form the mind and
feelings on an exclusively religious type, and discarding those
secular standards (as for want of a better name they may be called)
which heretofore coexisted with and supplemented the Christian
ethics, receiving some of its spirit, and infusing into it some
of theirs, there will result, and is even now resulting, a low,
abject, servile type of character, which, submit itself as it
may to what it deems the Supreme Will, is incapable of rising
to or sympathizing in the conception of Supreme Goodness. I believe
that other ethics than any one which can be evolved from exclusively
Christian sources, must exist side by side with Christian ethics
to produce the moral regeneration of mankind; and that the Christian
system is no exception to the rule that in an imperfect state
of the human mind, the interests of truth require a diversity
of opinions. It is not necessary that in ceasing to ignore the
moral truths not contained in Christianity, men should ignore
any of those which it does contain. Such prejudice, or oversight,
when it occurs, is altogether an evil; but it is one from which
we cannot hope to be always exempt, and must be regarded as the
price paid for an inestimable good. The exclusive pretension made
by a part of the truth to be the whole, must and ought to be protested
against, and if a reactionary impulse should make the protestors
unjust in their turn, this one-sidedness, like the other, may
be lamented, but must be tolerated. If Christians would teach
infidels to be just to Christianity, they should themselves be
just to infidelity. It can do truth no service to blink the fact,
known to all who have the most ordinary acquaintance with literary
history, that a large portion of the noblest and most valuable
moral teaching has been the work, not only of men who did not
know, but of men who knew and rejected, the Christian faith.
I do not pretend that the most unlimited use of the freedom of
enunciating all possible opinions would put an end to the evils
of religious or philosophical sectarianism. Every truth which
men of narrow capacity are in earnest about, is sure to be asserted,
inculcated, and in many ways even acted on, as if no other truth
existed in the world, or at all events none that could limit or
qualify the first. I acknowledge that the tendency of all opinions
to become sectarian is not cured by the freest discussion, but
is often heightened and exacerbated thereby; the truth which ought
to have been, but was not, seen, being rejected all the more violently
because proclaimed by persons regarded as opponents. But it is
not on the impassioned partisan, it is on the calmer and more
disinterested bystander, that this collision of opinions works
its salutary effect. Not the violent conflict between parts of
the truth, but the quiet suppression of half of it, is the formidable
evil: there is always hope when people are forced to listen to
both sides; it is when they attend only to one that errors harden
into prejudices, and truth itself ceases to have the effect of
truth, by being exaggerated into falsehood. And since there are
few mental attributes more rare than that judicial faculty which
can sit in intelligent judgment between two sides of a question,
of which only one is represented by an advocate before it, truth
has no chance but in proportion as every side of it, every opinion
which embodies any fraction of the truth, not only finds advocates,
but is so advocated as to be listened to.
We have now recognized the necessity to the mental wellbeing of
mankind (on which all their other well-being depends) of freedom
of opinion, and freedom of the expression of opinion, on four
distinct grounds; which we will now briefly recapitulate.
First, if any opinion is compelled to silence, that opinion may,
for aught we can certainly know, be true. To deny this is to assume
our own infallibility.
Secondly, though the silenced opinion be an error, it may, and
very commonly does, contain a portion of truth; and since the
general or prevailing opinion on any object is rarely or never
the whole truth, it is only by the collision of adverse opinions
that the remainder of the truth has any chance of being supplied.
Thirdly, even if the received opinion be not only true, but the
whole truth; unless it is suffered to be, and actually is, vigorously
and earnestly contested, it will, by most of those who receive
it, be held in the manner of a prejudice, with little comprehension
or feeling of its rational grounds. And not only this, but, fourthly,
the meaning of the doctrine itself will be in danger of being
lost, or enfeebled, and deprived of its vital effect on the character
and conduct: the dogma becoming a mere formal profession, inefficacious
for good, but cumbering the ground, and preventing the growth
of any real and heartfelt conviction, from reason or personal
experience.
Before quitting the subject of freedom of opinion, it is fit to
take notice of those who say, that the free expression of all
opinions should be permitted, on condition that the manner be
temperate, and do not pass the bounds of fair discussion. Much
might be said on the impossibility of fixing where these supposed
bounds are to be placed; for if the test be offence to those whose
opinion is attacked, I think experience testifies that this offence
is given whenever the attack is telling and powerful, and that
every opponent who pushes them hard, and whom they find it difficult
to answer, appears to them, if he shows any strong feeling on
the subject, an intemperate opponent. But this, though an important
consideration in a practical point of view, merges in a more fundamental
objection. Undoubtedly the manner of asserting an opinion, even
though it be a true one, may be very objectionable, and may justly
incur severe censure. But the principal offences of the kind are
such as it is mostly impossible, unless by accidental self-betrayal,
to bring home to conviction. The gravest of them is, to argue
sophistically, to suppress facts or arguments, to misstate the
elements of the case, or misrepresent the opposite opinion. But
all this, even to the most aggravated degree, is so continually
done in perfect good faith, by persons who are not considered,
and in many other respects may not deserve to be considered, ignorant
or incompetent, that it is rarely possible on adequate grounds
conscientiously to stamp the misrepresentation as morally culpable;
and still less could law presume to interfere with this kind of
controversial misconduct. With regard to what is commonly meant
by intemperate discussion, namely, invective, sarcasm, personality,
and the like, the denunciation of these weapons would deserve
more sympathy if it were ever proposed to interdict them equally
to both sides; but it is only desired to restrain the employment
of them against the prevailing opinion: against the unprevailing
they may not only be used without general disapproval, but will
be likely to obtain for him who uses them the praise of honest
zeal and righteous indignation. Yet whatever mischief arises from
their use, is greatest when they are employed against the comparatively
defenceless; and whatever unfair advantage can be derived by any
opinion from this mode of asserting it, accrues almost exclusively
to received opinions. The worst offence of this kind which can
be committed by a polemic, is to stigmatize those who hold the
contrary opinion as bad and immoral men. To calumny of this sort,
those who hold any unpopular opinion are peculiarly exposed, because
they are in general few and uninfluential, and nobody but themselves
feels much interest in seeing justice done them; but this weapon
is, from the nature of the case, denied to those who attack a
prevailing opinion: they can neither use it with safety to themselves,
nor if they could, would it do anything but recoil on their own
cause. In general, opinions contrary to those commonly received
can only obtain a hearing by studied moderation of language, and
the most cautious avoidance of unnecessary offence, from which
they hardly ever deviate even in a slight degree without losing
ground: while unmeasured vituperation employed on the side of
the prevailing opinion, really does deter people from professing
contrary opinions, and from listening to those who profess them.
For the interest, therefore, of truth and justice, it is far more
important to restrain this employment of vituperative language
than the other; and, for example, if it were necessary to choose,
there would be much more need to discourage offensive attacks
on infidelity, than on religion. It is, however, obvious that
law and authority have no business with restraining either, while
opinion ought, in every instance, to determine its verdict by
the circumstances of the individual case; condemning every one,
on whichever side of the argument he places himself, in whose
mode of advocacy either want of candor, or malignity, bigotry or intolerance of feeling manifest themselves, but not inferring
these vices from the side which a person takes, though it be the
contrary side of the question to our own; and giving merited honor
to every one, whatever opinion he may hold, who has calmness to
see and honesty to state what his opponents and their opinions
really are, exaggerating nothing to their discredit, keeping nothing
back which tells, or can be supposed to tell, in their favor.
This is the real morality of public discussion; and if often violated,
I am happy to think that there are many controversialists who
to a great extent observe it, and a still greater number who conscientiously
strive towards it. [1] These words had scarcely been written,
when, as if to give them an emphatic contradiction, occurred the
Government Press Prosecutions of 1858. That illjudged interference
with the liberty of public discussion has not, however, induced
me to alter a single word in the text, nor has it at all weakened
my conviction that, moments of panic excepted, the era of pains
and penalties far political discussion has, in our own country,
passed away. For, in the first place, the prosecutions were not
persisted in; and in the second, they were never, properly speaking,
political prosecutions. The offence charged was not that of criticizing
institutions, or the acts or persons of rulers, but of circulating
what was deemed an immoral doctrine, the lawfulness of Tyrannicide.
If the arguments of the present chapter are of any validity, there
ought to exist the fullest liberty of professing and discussing,
as a matter of ethical conviction, any doctrine, however immoral
it may be considered. It would, therefore, be irrelevant and out
of place to examine here, whether the doctrine of Tyrannicide
deserves that title. I shall content myself with saying, that
the subject has been at all times one of the open questions of
morals, that the act of a private citizen in striking down a criminal,
who, by raising himself above the law, has placed himself beyond
the reach of legal punishment or control, has been accounted by
whole nations, and by some of the best and wisest of men, not
a crime, but an act of exalted virtue and that, right or wrong,
it is not of the nature of assassination but of civil war. As
such, I hold that the instigation to it, in a specific case, may
be a proper subject of punishment, but only if an overt act has
followed, and at least a probable connection can be established
between the act and the instigation. Even then it is not a foreign
government, but the very government assailed, which alone, in
the exercise of self-defence, can legitimately punish attacks
directed against its own existence. [2] Thomas Pooley, Bodmin
Assizes, July 31, 1857. In December following, he received a free
pardon from the Crown. [3] George Jacob Holyoake, August 17, 1857;
Edward Truelove, July, 1857. [4] Baron de Gleichen, Marlborough
Street Police Court, August 4, 1857. [5] Ample warning may be
drawn from the large infusion of the passions of a persecutor,
which mingled with the general display of the worst parts of our
national character on the occasion of the Sepoy insurrection.
The ravings of fanatics or charlatans from the pulpit may be unworthy
of notice; but the heads of the Evangelical party have announced
as their principle, for the government of Hindoos and Mahomedans,
that no schools be supported by public money in which the Bible
is not taught, and by necessary consequence that no public employment
be given to any but real or pretended Christians. An Under-Secretary
of State, in a speech delivered to his constituents on the 12th
of November, 1857, is reported to have said: "Toleration
of their faith" (the faith of a hundred millions of British
subjects), "the superstition which they called religion,
by the British Government, had had the effect of retarding the
ascendency of the British name, and preventing the salutary growth
of Christianity.... Toleration was the great corner-stone of the
religious liberties of this country; but do not let them abuse
that precious word toleration. As he understood it, it meant the
complete liberty to all, freedom of worship, among Christians,
who worshipped upon the same foundation. It meant toleration of
all sects and denominations of Christians who believed in the
one mediation." I desire to call attention to the fact, that
a man who has been deemed fit to fill a high office in the government
of this country, under a liberal Ministry, maintains the doctrine
that all who do not believe in the divinity of Christ are beyond
the pale of toleration. Who, after this imbecile display, can
indulge the illusion that religious persecution has passed away,
never to return?
CHAPTER III ON INDIVIDUALITY, AS ONE OF THE ELEMENTS OF WELLBEING
SUCH being the reasons which make it imperative that human beings
should be free to form opinions, and to express their opinions
without reserve; and such the baneful consequences to the intellectual,
and through that to the moral nature of man, unless this liberty
is either conceded, or asserted in spite of prohibition; let us
next examine whether the same reasons do not require that men
should be free to act upon their opinions--to carry these out
in their lives, without hindrance, either physical or moral, from
their fellow-men, so long as it is at their own risk and peril.
This last proviso is of course indispensable. No one pretends
that actions should be as free as opinions. On the contrary, even
opinions lose their immunity, when the circumstances in which
they are expressed are such as to constitute their expression
a positive instigation to some mischievous act. An opinion that
corndealers are starvers of the poor, or that private property
is robbery, ought to be unmolested when simply circulated through
the press, but may justly incur punishment when delivered orally
to an excited mob assembled before the house of a corn-dealer,
or when handed about among the same mob in the form of a placard.
Acts of whatever kind, which, without justifiable cause, do harm
to others, may be, and in the more important cases absolutely
require to be, controlled by the unfavorable sentiments, and,
when needful, by the active interference of mankind. The liberty
of the individual must be thus far limited; he must not make himself
a nuisance to other people. But if he refrains from molesting
others in what concerns them, and merely acts according to his
own inclination and judgment in things which concern himself,
the same reasons which show that opinion should be free, prove
also that he should be allowed, without molestation, to carry
his opinions into practice at his own cost. That mankind are not
infallible; that their truths, for the most part, are only half-truths;
that unity of opinion, unless resulting from the fullest and freest
comparison of opposite opinions, is not desirable, and diversity
not an evil, but a good, until mankind are much more capable than
at present of recognizing all sides of the truth, are principles
applicable to men's modes of action, not less than to their opinions.
As it is useful that while mankind are imperfect there should
be different opinions, so is it that there should be different
experiments of living; that free scope should be given to varieties
of character, short of injury to others; and that the worth of
different modes of life should be proved practically, when any
one thinks fit to try them. It is desirable, in short, that in
things which do not primarily concern others, individuality should
assert itself. Where, not the person's own character, but the
traditions of customs of other people are the rule of conduct,
there is wanting one of the principal ingredients of human happiness,
and quite the chief ingredient of individual and social progress.
In maintaining this principle, the greatest difficulty to be encountered
does not lie in the appreciation of means towards an acknowledged
end, but in the indifference of persons in general to the end
itself. If it were felt that the free development of individuality
is one of the leading essentials of well-being; that it is not
only a coordinate element with all that is designated by the terms
civilization, instruction, education, culture, but is itself a
necessary part and condition of all those things; there would
be no danger that liberty should be undervalued, and the adjustment
of the boundaries between it and social control would present
no extraordinary difficulty. But the evil is, that individual
spontaneity is hardly recognized by the common modes of thinking
as having any intrinsic worth, or deserving any regard on its
own account. The majority, being satisfied with the ways of mankind
as they now are (for it is they who make them what they are),
cannot comprehend why those ways should not be good enough for
everybody; and what is more, spontaneity forms no part of the
ideal of the majority of moral and social reformers, but is rather
looked on with jealousy, as a troublesome and perhaps rebellious
obstruction to the general acceptance of what these reformers,
in their own judgment, think would be best for mankind. Few persons,
out of Germany, even comprehend the meaning of the doctrine which
Wilhelm von Humboldt, so eminent both as a savant and as a politician,
made the text of a treatise-that "the end of man, or that
which is prescribed by the eternal or immutable dictates of reason,
and not suggested by vague and transient desires, is the highest
and most harmonious development of his powers to a complete and
consistent whole;" that, therefore, the object "towards
which every human being must ceaselessly direct his efforts, and
on which especially those who design to influence their fellow-men
must ever keep their eyes, is the individuality of power and development;"
that for this there are two requisites, "freedom, and a variety
of situations;" and that from the union of these arise "individual
vigor and manifold diversity," which combine themselves in
"originality."[1]
Little, however, as people are accustomed to a doctrine like that
of Von Humboldt, and surprising as it may be to them to find so
high a value attached to individuality, the question, one must
nevertheless think, can only be one of degree. No one's idea of
excellence in conduct is that people should do absolutely nothing
but copy one another. No one would assert that people ought not
to put into their mode of life, and into the conduct of their
concerns, any impress whatever of their own judgment, or of their
own individual character. On the other hand, it would be absurd
to pretend that people ought to live as if nothing whatever had
been known in the world before they came into it; as if experience
had as yet done nothing towards showing that one mode of existence,
or of conduct, is preferable to another. Nobody denies that people
should be so taught and trained in youth, as to know and benefit
by the ascertained results of human experience. But it is the
privilege and proper condition of a human being, arrived at the
maturity of his faculties, to use and interpret experience in
his own way. It is for him to find out what part of recorded experience
is properly applicable to his own circumstances and character.
The traditions and customs of other people are, to a certain extent,
evidence of what their experience has taught them; presumptive
evidence, and as such, have a claim to this deference: but, in
the first place, their experience may be too narrow; or they may
not have interpreted it rightly. Secondly, their interpretation
of experience may be correct but unsuitable to him. Customs are
made for customary circumstances, and customary characters: and
his circumstances or his character may be uncustomary. Thirdly,
though the customs be both good as customs, and suitable to him,
yet to conform to custom, merely as custom, does not educate or
develop in him any of the qualities which are the distinctive
endowment of a human being. The human faculties of perception,
judgment, discriminative feeling, mental activity, and even moral
preference, are exercised only in making a choice. He who does
anything because it is the custom, makes no choice. He gains no
practice either in discerning or in desiring what is best. The
mental and moral, like the muscular powers, are improved only
by being used. The faculties are called into no exercise by doing
a thing merely because others do it, no more than by believing
a thing only because others believe it. If the grounds of an opinion
are not conclusive to the person's own reason, his reason cannot
be strengthened, but is likely to be weakened by his adopting
it: and if the inducements to an act are not such as are consentaneous
to his own feelings and character (where affection, or the rights
of others are not concerned), it is so much done towards rendering
his feelings and character inert and torpid, instead of active
and energetic.
He who lets the world, or his own portion of it, choose his plan
of life for him, has no need of any other faculty than the ape-like
one of imitation. He who chooses his plan for himself, employs
all his faculties. He must use observation to see, reasoning and
judgment to foresee, activity to gather materials for decision,
discrimination to decide, and when he has decided, firmness and
self-control to hold to his deliberate decision. And these qualities
he requires and exercises exactly in proportion as the part of
his conduct which he determines according to his own judgment
and feelings is a large one. It is possible that he might be guided
in some good path, and kept out of harm's way, without any of
these things. But what will be his comparative worth as a human
being? It really is of importance, not only what men do, but also
what manner of men they are that do it. Among the works of man,
which human life is rightly employed in perfecting and beautifying,
the first in importance surely is man himself. Supposing it were
possible to get houses built, corn grown, battles fought, causes
tried, and even churches erected and prayers said, by machinery--by
automatons in human form--it would be a considerable loss to exchange
for these automatons even the men and women who at present inhabit
the more civilized parts of the world, and who assuredly are but
starved specimens of what nature can and will produce. Human nature
is not a machine to be built after a model, and set to do exactly
the work prescribed for it, but a tree, which requires to grow
and develop itself on all sides, according to the tendency of
the inward forces which make it a living thing.
It will probably be conceded that it is desirable people should
exercise their understandings, and that an intelligent following
of custom, or even occasionally an intelligent deviation from
custom, is better than a blind and simply mechanical adhesion
to it. To a certain extent it is admitted, that our understanding
should be our own: but there is not the same willingness to admit
that our desires and impulses should be our own likewise; or that
to possess impulses of our own, and of any strength, is anything
but a peril and a snare. Yet desires and impulses are as much
a part of a perfect human being, as beliefs and restraints: and
strong impulses are only perilous when not properly balanced;
when one set of aims and inclinations is developed into strength,
while others, which ought to coexist with them, remain weak and
inactive. It is not because men's desires are strong that they
act ill; it is because their consciences are weak. There is no
natural connection between strong impulses and a weak conscience.
The natural connection is the other way. To say that one person's
desires and feelings are stronger and more various than those
of another, is merely to say that he has more of the raw material
of human nature, and is therefore capable, perhaps of more evil,
but certainly of more good. Strong impulses are but another name
for energy. Energy may be turned to bad uses; but more good may
always be made of an energetic nature, than of an indolent and
impassive one. Those who have most natural feeling, are always
those whose cultivated feelings may be made the strongest. The
same strong susceptibilities which make the personal impulses
vivid and powerful, are also the source from whence are generated
the most passionate love of virtue, and the sternest selfcontrol.
It is through the cultivation of these, that society both does
its duty and protects its interests: not by rejecting the stuff
of which heroes are made, because it knows not how to make them.
A person whose desires and impulses are his own--are the expression
of his own nature, as it has been developed and modified by his
own culture--is said to have a character. One whose desires and
impulses are not his owN, has no character, no more than a steam-engine
has a character. If, in addition to being his own, his impulses
are strong, and are under the government of a strong will, he
has an energetic character. Whoever thinks that individuality
of desires and impulses should not be encouraged to unfold itself,
must maintain that society has no need of strong natures--is not
the better for containing many persons who have much character--and
that a high general average of energy is not desirable.
In some early states of society, these forces might be, and were,
too much ahead of the power which society then possessed of disciplining
and controlling them. There has been a time when the element of
spontaneity and individuality was in excess, and the social principle
had a hard struggle with it. The difficulty then was, to induce
men of strong bodies or minds to pay obedience to any rules which
required them to control their impulses. To overcome this difficulty,
law and discipline, like the Popes struggling against the Emperors,
asserted a power over the whole man, claiming to control all his
life in order to control his character-which society had not found
any other sufficient means of binding. But society has now fairly
got the better of individuality; and the danger which threatens
human nature is not the excess, but the deficiency, of personal
impulses and preferences. Things are vastly changed, since the
passions of those who were strong by station or by personal endowment
were in a state of habitual rebellion against laws and ordinances,
and required to be rigorously chained up to enable the persons
within their reach to enjoy any particle of security. In our times,
from the highest class of society down to the lowest every one
lives as under the eye of a hostile and dreaded censorship. Not
only in what concerns others, but in what concerns only themselves,
the individual, or the family, do not ask themselves--what do
I prefer? or, what would suit my character and disposition? or,
what would allow the best and highest in me to have fair play,
and enable it to grow and thrive? They ask themselves, what is
suitable to my position? what is usually done by persons of my
station and pecuniary circumstances? or (worse still) what is
usually done by persons of a station and circumstances superior
to mine? I do not mean that they choose what is customary, in
preference to what suits their own inclination. It does not occur
to them to have any inclination, except for what is customary.
Thus the mind itself is bowed to the yoke: even in what people
do for pleasure, conformity is the first thing thought of; they
like in crowds; they exercise choice only among things commonly
done: peculiarity of taste, eccentricity of conduct, are shunned
equally with crimes: until by dint of not following their own
nature, they have no nature to follow: their human capacities
are withered and starved: they become incapable of any strong
wishes or native pleasures, and are generally without either opinions
or feelings of home growth, or properly their own. Now is this,
or is it not, the desirable condition of human nature?
It is so, on the Calvinistic theory. According to that, the one
great offence of man is Self-will. All the good of which humanity
is capable, is comprised in Obedience. You have no choice; thus
you must do, and no otherwise; "whatever is not a duty is
a sin." Human nature being radically corrupt, there is no
redemption for any one until human nature is killed within him.
To one holding this theory of life, crushing out any of the human
faculties, capacities, and susceptibilities, is no evil: man needs
no capacity, but that of surrendering himself to the will of God:
and if he uses any of his faculties for any other purpose but
to do that supposed will more effectually, he is better without
them. That is the theory of Calvinism; and it is held, in a mitigated
form, by many who do not consider themselves Calvinists; the mitigation
consisting in giving a less ascetic interpretation to the alleged
will of God; asserting it to be his will that mankind should gratify
some of their inclinations; of course not in the manner they themselves
prefer, but in the way of obedience, that is, in a way prescribed
to them by authority; and, therefore, by the necessary conditions
of the case, the same for all.
In some such insidious form there is at present a strong tendency
to this narrow theory of life, and to the pinched and hidebound
type of human character which it patronizes. Many persons, no
doubt, sincerely think that human beings thus cramped and dwarfed,
are as their Maker designed them to be; just as many have thought
that trees are a much finer thing when clipped into pollards,
or cut out into figures of animals, than as nature made them.
But if it be any part of religion to believe that man was made
by a good Being, it is more consistent with that faith to believe,
that this Being gave all human faculties that they might be cultivated
and unfolded, not rooted out and consumed, and that he takes delight
in every nearer approach made by his creatures to the ideal conception
embodied in them, every increase in any of their capabilities
of comprehension, of action, or of enjoyment. There is a different
type of human excellence from the Calvinistic; a conception of
humanity as having its nature bestowed on it for other purposes
than merely to be abnegated. "Pagan selfassertion" is
one of the elements of human worth, as well as "Christian
self-denial."[2] There is a Greek ideal of self-development,
which the Platonic and Christian ideal of self-government blends
with, but does not supersede. It may be better to be a John Knox
than an Alcibiades, but it is better to be a Pericles than either;
nor would a Pericles, if we had one in these days, be without
anything good which belonged to John Knox.
It is not by wearing down into uniformity all that is individual
in themselves, but by cultivating it and calling it forth, within
the limits imposed by the rights and interests of others, that
human beings become a noble and beautiful object of contemplation;
and as the works partake the character of those who do them, by
the same process human life also becomes rich, diversified, and
animating, furnishing more abundant aliment to high thoughts and
elevating feelings, and strengthening the tie which binds every
individual to the race, by making the race infinitely better worth
belonging to. In proportion to the development of his individuality,
each person becomes more valuable to himself, and is therefore
capable of being more valuable to others. There is a greater fulness
of life about his own existence, and when there is more life in
the units there is more in the mass which is composed of them.
As much compression as is necessary to prevent the stronger specimens
of human nature from encroaching on the rights of others, cannot
be dispensed with; but for this there is ample compensation even
in the point of view of human development. The means of development
which the individual loses by being prevented from gratifying
his inclinations to the injury of others, are chiefly obtained
at the expense of the development of other people. And even to
himself there is a full equivalent in the better development of
the social part of his nature, rendered possible by the restraint
put upon the selfish part. To be held to rigid rules of justice
for the sake of others, develops the feelings and capacities which
have the good of others for their object. But to be restrained
in things not affecting their good, by their mere displeasure,
develops nothing valuable, except such force of character as may
unfold itself in resisting the restraint. If acquiesced in, it
dulls and blunts the whole nature. To give any fair play to the
nature of each, it is essential that different persons should
be allowed to lead different lives. In proportion as this latitude
has been exercised in any age, has that age been noteworthy to
posterity. Even despotism does not produce its worst effects,
so long as Individuality exists under it; and whatever crushes
individuality is despotism, by whatever name it may be called,
and whether it professes to be enforcing the will of God or the
injunctions of men.
Having said that Individuality is the same thing with development,
and that it is only the cultivation of individuality which produces,
or can produce, well-developed human beings, I might here close
the argument: for what more or better can be said of any condition
of human affairs, than that it brings human beings themselves
nearer to the best thing they can be? or what worse can be said
of any obstruction to good, than that it prevents this? Doubtless,
however, these considerations will not suffice to convince those
who most need convincing; and it is necessary further to show,
that these developed human beings are of some use to the undeveloped--to
point out to those who do not desire liberty, and would not avail
themselves of it, that they may be in some intelligible manner
rewarded for allowing other people to make use of it without hindrance.
In the first place, then, I would suggest that they might possibly
learn something from them. It will not be denied by anybody, that
originality is a valuable element in human affairs. There is always
need of persons not only to discover new truths, and point out
when what were once truths are true no longer, but also to commence
new practices, and set the example of more enlightened conduct,
and better taste and sense in human life. This cannot well be
gainsaid by anybody who does not believe that the world has already
attained perfection in all its ways and practices. It is true
that this benefit is not capable of being rendered by everybody
alike: there are but few persons, in comparison with the whole
of mankind, whose experiments, if adopted by others, would be
likely to be any improvement on established practice. But these
few are the salt of the earth; without them, human life would
become a stagnant pool. Not only is it they who introduce good
things which did not before exist; it is they who keep the life
in those which already existed. If there were nothing new to be
done, would human intellect cease to be necessary? Would it be
a reason why those who do the old things should forget why they
are done, and do them like cattle, not like human beings? There
is only too great a tendency in the best beliefs and practices
to degenerate into the mechanical; and unless there were a succession
of persons whose ever-recurring originality prevents the grounds
of those beliefs and practices from becoming merely traditional,
such dead matter would not resist the smallest shock from anything
really alive, and there would be no reason why civilization should
not die out, as in the Byzantine Empire. Persons of genius, it
is true, are, and are always likely to be, a small minority; but
in order to have them, it is necessary to preserve the soil in
which they grow. Genius can only breathe freely in an atmosphere
of freedom. Persons of genius are, ex vi termini, more individual
than any other people--less capable, consequently, of fitting
themselves, without hurtful compression, into any of the small
number of moulds which society provides in order to save its members
the trouble of forming their own character. If from timidity they
consent to be forced into one of these moulds, and to let all
that part of themselves which cannot expand under the pressure
remain unexpanded, society will be little the better for their
genius. If they are of a strong character, and break their fetters
they become a mark for the society which has not succeeded in
reducing them to common-place, to point at with solemn warning
as "wild," "erratic," and the like; much as
if one should complain of the Niagara river for not flowing smoothly
between its banks like a Dutch canal.
I insist thus emphatically on the importance of genius, and the
necessity of allowing it to unfold itself freely both in thought
and in practice, being well aware that no one will deny the position
in theory, but knowing also that almost every one, in reality,
is totally indifferent to it. People think genius a fine thing
if it enables a man to write an exciting poem, or paint a picture.
But in its true sense, that of originality in thought and action,
though no one says that it is not a thing to be admired, nearly
all, at heart, think they can do very well without it. Unhappily
this is too natural to be wondered at. Originality is the one
thing which unoriginal minds cannot feel the use of. They cannot
see what it is to do for them: how should they? If they could
see what it would do for them, it would not be originality. The
first service which originality has to render them, is that of
opening their eyes: which being once fully done, they would have
a chance of being themselves original. Meanwhile, recollecting
that nothing was ever yet done which some one was not the first
to do, and that all good things which exist are the fruits of
originality, let them be modest enough to believe that there is
something still left for it to accomplish, and assure themselves
that they are more in need of originality, the less they are conscious
of the want.
In sober truth, whatever homage may be professed, or even paid,
to real or supposed mental superiority, the general tendency of
things throughout the world is to render mediocrity the ascendant
power among mankind. In ancient history, in the Middle Ages, and
in a diminishing degree through the long transition from feudality
to the present time, the individual was a power in himself; and
If he had either great talents or a high social position, he was
a considerable power. At present individuals are lost in the crowd.
In politics it is almost a triviality to say that public opinion
now rules the world. The only power deserving the name is that
of masses, and of governments while they make themselves the organ
of the tendencies and instincts of masses. This is as true in
the moral and social relations of private life as in public transactions.
Those whose opinions go by the name of public opinion, are not
always the same sort of public: in America, they are the whole
white population; in England, chiefly the middle class. But they
are always a mass, that is to say, collective mediocrity. And
what is still greater novelty, the mass do not now take their
opinions from dignitaries in Church or State, from ostensible
leaders, or from books. Their thinking is done for them by men
much like themselves, addressing them or speaking in their name,
on the spur of the moment, through the newspapers. I am not complaining
of all this. I do not assert that anything better is compatible,
as a general rule, with the present low state of the human mind.
But that does not hinder the government of mediocrity from being
mediocre government. No government by a democracy or a numerous
aristocracy, either in its political acts or in the opinions,
qualities, and tone of mind which it fosters, ever did or could
rise above mediocrity, except in so far as the sovereign Many
have let themselves be guided (which in their best times they
always have done) by the counsels and influence of a more highly
gifted and instructed One or Few. The initiation of all wise or
noble things, comes and must come from individuals; generally
at first from some one individual. The honor and glory of the
average man is that he is capable of following that initiative;
that he can respond internally to wise and noble things, and be
led to them with his eyes open. I am not countenancing the sort
of "hero-worship" which applauds the strong man of genius
for forcibly seizing on the government of the world and making
it do his bidding in spite of itself. All he can claim is, freedom
to point out the way. The power of compelling others into it,
is not only inconsistent with the freedom and development of all
the rest, but corrupting to the strong man himself. It does seem,
however, that when the opinions of masses of merely average men
are everywhere become or becoming the dominant power, the counterpoise
and corrective to that tendency would be, the more and more pronounced
individuality of those who stand on the higher eminences of thought.
It Is in these circumstances most especially, that exceptional
individuals, instead of being deterred, should be encouraged in
acting differently from the mass. In other times there was no
advantage in their doing so, unless they acted not only differently,
but better. In this age the mere example of non-conformity, the
mere refusal to bend the knee to custom, is itself a service.
Precisely because the tyranny of opinion is such as to make eccentricity
a reproach, it is desirable, in order to break through that tyranny,
that people should be eccentric. Eccentricity has always abounded
when and where strength of character has abounded; and the amount
of eccentricity in a society has generally been proportional to
the amount of genius, mental vigor, and moral courage which it
contained. That so few now dare to be eccentric, marks the chief
danger of the time.
I have said that it is important to give the freest scope possible
to uncustomary things, in order that it may in time appear which
of these are fit to be converted into customs. But independence
of action, and disregard of custom are not solely deserving of
encouragement for the chance they afford that better modes of
action, and customs more worthy of general adoption, may be struck
out; nor is it only persons of decided mental superiority who
have a just claim to carry on their lives in their own way. There
is no reason that all human existences should be constructed on
some one, or some small number of patterns. If a person possesses
any tolerable amount of common sense and experience, his own mode
of laying out his existence is the best, not because it is the
best in itself, but because it is his own mode. Human beings are
not like sheep; and even sheep are not undistinguishably alike.
A man cannot get a coat or a pair of boots to fit him, unless
they are either made to his measure, or he has a whole warehouseful
to choose from: and is it easier to fit him with a life than with
a coat, or are human beings more like one another in their whole
physical and spiritual conformation than in the shape of their
feet? If it were only that people have diversities of taste that
is reason enough for not attempting to shape them all after one
model. But different persons also require different conditions
for their spiritual development; and can no more exist healthily
in the same moral, than all the variety of plants can in the same
physical atmosphere and climate. The same things which are helps
to one person towards the cultivation of his higher nature, are
hindrances to another. The same mode of life is a healthy excitement
to one, keeping all his faculties of action and enjoyment in their
best order, while to another it is a distracting burden, which
suspends or crushes all internal life. Such are the differences
among human beings in their sources of pleasure, their susceptibilities
of pain, and the operation on them of different physical and moral
agencies, that unless there is a corresponding diversity in their
modes of life, they neither obtain their fair share of happiness,
nor grow up to the mental, moral, and aesthetic stature of which
their nature is capable. Why then should tolerance, as far as
the public sentiment is concerned, extend only to tastes and modes
of life which extort acquiescence by the multitude of their society.
Though society is not founded on a contract, and though no good
purpose is answered by inventing a contract in order to deduce
social obligations from it, every one who receives the protection
of society owes a return for the benefit, and the fact of living
in society renders it indispensable that each should be bound
to observe a certain line of conduct towards the rest. This conduct
consists, first, in not injuring the interests of one another;
or rather certain interests, which, either by express legal provision
or by tacit understanding, ought to be considered as rights; and
secondly, in each person's bearing his share (to be fixed on some
equitable principle) of the labors and sacrifices incurred for
defending the society or its members from injury and molestation.
These conditions society is justified in enforcing, at all costs
to those who endeavor to withhold fulfilment. Nor is this all
that society may do. The acts of an individual may be hurtful
to others, or wanting in due consideration for their welfare,
without going the length of violating any of their constituted
rights. The offender may then be justly punished by opinion, though
not by law. As soon as any part of a person's conduct affects
prejudicially the interests of others, society has jurisdiction
over it, and the question whether the general welfare will or
will not be promoted by interfering with it, becomes open to discussion.
But there is no room for entertaining any such question when a
person's conduct affects the interests of no persons besides himself,
or needs not affect them unless they like (all the persons concerned
being of full age, and the ordinary amount of understanding).
In all such cases there should be perfect freedom, legal and social,
to do the action and stand the consequences.
It would be a great misunderstanding of this doctrine, to suppose
that it is one of selfish indifference, which pretends that human
beings have no business with each other's conduct in life, and
that they should not concern themselves about the well-doing or
well-being of one another, unless their own interest is involved.
Instead of any diminution, there is need of a great increase of
disinterested exertion to promote the good of others. But disinterested
benevolence can find other instruments to persuade people to their
good, than whips and scourges, either of the literal or the metaphorical
sort. I am the last person to undervalue the self-regarding virtues;
they are only second in importance, if even second, to the social.
It is equally the business of education to cultivate both. But
even education works by conviction and persuasion as well as by
compulsion, and it is by the former only that, when the period
of education is past, the self-regarding virtues should be inculcated.
Human beings owe to each other help to distinguish the better
from the worse, and encouragement to choose the former and avoid
the latter. They should be forever stimulating each other to increased
exercise of their higher faculties, and increased direction of
their feelings and aims towards wise instead of foolish, elevating
instead of degrading, objects and contemplations. But neither
one person, nor any number of persons, is warranted in saying
to another human creature of ripe years, that he shall not do
with his life for his own benefit what he chooses to do with it.
He is the person most interested in his own well-being, the interest
which any other person, except in cases of strong personal attachment,
can have in it, is trifling, compared with that which he himself
has; the interest which society has in him individually (except
as to his conduct to others) is fractional, and altogether indirect:
while, with respect to his own feelings and circumstances, the
most ordinary man or woman has means of knowledge immeasurably
surpassing those that can be possessed by any one else. The interference
of society to overrule his judgment and purposes in what only
regards himself, must be grounded on general presumptions; which
may be altogether wrong, and even if right, are as likely as not
to be misapplied to individual cases, by persons no better acquainted
with the circumstances of such cases than those are who look at
them merely from without. In this department, therefore, of human
affairs, Individuality has its proper field of action. In the
conduct of human beings towards one another, it is necessary that
general rules should for the most part be observed, in order that
people may know what they have to expect; but in each person's
own concerns, his individual spontaneity is entitled to free exercise.
Considerations to aid his judgment, exhortations to strengthen
his will, may be offered to him, even obtruded on him, by others;
but he, himself, is the final judge. All errors which he is likely
to commit against advice and warning, are far outweighed by the
evil of allowing others to constrain him to what they deem his
good.
I do not mean that the feelings with which a person is regarded
by others, ought not to be in any way affected by his self-regarding
qualities or deficiencies. This is neither possible nor desirable.
If he is eminent in any of the qualities which conduce to his
own good, he is, so far, a proper object of admiration. He is
so much the nearer to the ideal perfection of human nature. If
he is grossly deficient in those qualities, a sentiment the opposite
of admiration will follow. There is a degree of folly, and a degree
of what may be called (though the phrase is not unobjectionable)
lowness or depravation of taste, which, though it cannot justify
doing harm to the person who manifests it, renders him necessarily
and properly a subject of distaste, or, in extreme cases, even
of contempt: a person could not have the opposite qualities in
due strength without entertaining these feelings. Though doing
no wrong to any one, a person may so act as to compel us to judge
him, and feel to him, as a fool, or as a being of an inferior
order: and since this judgment and feeling are a fact which he
would prefer to avoid, it is doing him a service to warn him of
it beforehand, as of any other disagreeable consequence to which
he exposes himself. It would be well, indeed, if this good office
were much more freely rendered than the common notions of politeness
at present permit, and if one person could honestly point out
to another that he thinks him in fault, without being considered
unmannerly or presuming. We have a right, also, in various ways,
to act upon our unfavorable opinion of any one, not to the oppression
of his individuality, but in the exercise of ours. We are not
bound, for example, to seek his society; we have a right to avoid
it (though not to parade the avoidance), for we have a right to
choose the society most acceptable to us. We have a right, and
it may be our duty, to caution others against him, if we think
his example or conversation likely to have a pernicious effect
on those with whom he associates. We may give others a preference
over him in optional good offices, except those which tend to
his improvement. In these various modes a person may suffer very
severe penalties at the hands of others, for faults which directly
concern only himself; but he suffers these penalties only in so
far as they are the natural, and, as it were, the spontaneous
consequences of the faults themselves, not because they are purposely
inflicted on him for the sake of punishment. A person who shows
rashness, obstinacy, self-conceit--who cannot live within moderate
means--who cannot restrain himself from hurtful indulgences--who
pursues animal pleasures at the expense of those of feeling and
intellect--must expect to be lowered in the opinion of others,
and to have a less share of their favorable sentiments, but of
this he has no right to complain, unless he has merited their
favor by special excellence in his social relations, and has thus
established a title to their good offices, which is not affected
by his demerits towards himself.
What I contend for is, that the inconveniences which are strictly
inseparable from the unfavorable judgment of others, are the only
ones to which a person should ever be subjected for that portion
of his conduct and character which concerns his own good, but
which does not affect the interests of others in their relations
with him. Acts injurious to others require a totally different
treatment. Encroachment on their rights; infliction on them of
any loss or damage not justified by his own rights; falsehood
or duplicity in dealing with them; unfair or ungenerous use of
advantages over them; even selfish abstinence from defending them
against injury--these are fit objects of moral reprobation, and,
in grave cases, of moral retribution and punishment. And not only
these acts, but the dispositions which lead to them, are properly
immoral, and fit subjects of disapprobation which may rise to
abhorrence. Cruelty of disposition; malice and ill-nature; that
most anti-social and odious of all passions, envy; dissimulation
and insincerity, irascibility on insufficient cause, and resentment
disproportioned to the provocation; the love of domineering over
others; the desire to engross more than one's share of advantages
(the [greekword] of the Greeks); the pride which derives gratification
from the abasement of others; the egotism which thinks self and
its concerns more important than everything else, and decides
all doubtful questions in his own favor;--these are moral vices,
and constitute a bad and odious moral character: unlike the self-regarding
faults previously mentioned, which are not properly immoralities,
and to whatever pitch they may be carried, do not constitute wickedness.
They may be proofs of any amount of folly, or want of personal
dignity and self-respect; but they are only a subject of moral
reprobation when they involve a breach of duty to others, for
whose sake the individual is bound to have care for himself. What
are called duties to ourselves are not socially obligatory, unless
circumstances render them at the same time duties to others. The
term duty to oneself, when it means anything more than prudence,
means self-respect or self-development; and for none of these
is any one accountable to his fellow-creatures, because for none
of them is it for the good of mankind that he be held accountable
to them.
The distinction between the loss of consideration which a person
may rightly incur by defect of prudence or of personal dignity,
and the reprobation which is due to him for an offence against
the rights of others, is not a merely nominal distinction. It
makes a vast difference both in our feelings and in our conduct
towards him, whether he displeases us in things in which we think
we have a right to control him, or in things in which we know
that we have not. If he displeases us, we may express our distaste,
and we may stand aloof from a person as well as from a thing that
displeases us; but we shall not therefore feel called on to make
his life uncomfortable. We shall reflect that he already bears,
or will bear, the whole penalty of his error; if he spoils his
life by mismanagement, we shall not, for that reason, desire to
spoil it still further: instead of wishing to punish him, we shall
rather endeavor to alleviate his punishment, by showing him how
he may avoid or cure the evils his conduct tends to bring upon
him. He may be to us an object of pity, perhaps of dislike, but
not of anger or resentment; we shall not treat him like an enemy
of society: the worst we shall think ourselves justified in doing
is leaving him to himself, If we do not interfere benevolently
by showing interest or concern for him. It is far otherwise if
he has infringed the rules necessary for the protection of his
fellow-creatures, individually or collectively. The evil consequences
of his acts do not then fall on himself, but on others; and society,
as the protector of all its members, must retaliate on him; must
inflict pain on him for the express purpose of punishment, and
must take care that it be sufficiently severe. In the one case,
he is an offender at our bar, and we are called on not only to
sit in judgment on him, but, in one shape or another, to execute
our own sentence: in the other case, it is not our part to inflict
any suffering on him, except what may incidentally follow from
our using the same liberty in the regulation of our own affairs,
which we allow to him in his.
The distinction here pointed out between the part of a person's
life which concerns only himself, and that which concerns others,
many persons will refuse to admit. How (it may be asked) can any
part of the conduct of a member of society be a matter of indifference
to the other members? No person is an entirely isolated being;
it is impossible for a person to do anything seriously or permanently
hurtful to himself, without mischief reaching at least to his
near connections, and often far beyond them. If he injures his
property, he does harm to those who directly or indirectly derived
support from it, and usually diminishes, by a greater or less
amount, the general resources of the community. If he deteriorates
his bodily or mental faculties, he not only brings evil upon all
who depended on him for any portion of their happiness, but disqualifies
himself for rendering the services which he owes to his fellow-creatures
generally; perhaps becomes a burden on their affection or benevolence;
and if such conduct were very frequent, hardly any offence that
is committed would detract more from the general sum of good.
Finally, if by his vices or follies a person does no direct harm
to others, he is nevertheless (it may be said) injurious by his
example; and ought to be compelled to control himself, for the
sake of those whom the sight or knowledge of his conduct might
corrupt or mislead.
And even (it will be added) if the consequences of misconduct
could be confined to the vicious or thoughtless individual, ought
society to abandon to their own guidance those who are manifestly
unfit for it? If protection against themselves is confessedly
due to children and persons under age, is not society equally
bound to afford it to persons of mature years who are equally
incapable of self-government? If gambling, or drunkenness, or
incontinence, or idleness, or uncleanliness, are as injurious
to happiness, and as great a hindrance to improvement, as many
or most of the acts prohibited by law, why (it may be asked) should
not law, so far as is consistent with practicability and social
convenience, endeavor to repress these also? And as a supplement
to the unavoidable imperfections of law, ought not opinion at
least to organize a powerful police against these vices, and visit
rigidly with social penalties those who are known to practise
them? There is no question here (it may be said) about restricting
individuality, or impeding the trial of new and original experiments
in living. The only things it is sought to prevent are things
which have been tried and condemned from the beginning of the
world until now; things which experience has shown not to be useful
or suitable to any person's individuality. There must be some
length of time and amount of experience, after which a moral or
prudential truth may be regarded as established, and it is merely
desired to prevent generation after generation from falling over
the same precipice which has been fatal to their predecessors.
I fully admit that the mischief which a person does to himself,
may seriously affect, both through their sympathies and their
interests, those nearly connected with him, and in a minor degree,
society at large. When, by conduct of this sort, a person is led
to violate a distinct and assignable obligation to any other person
or persons, the case is taken out of the self-regarding class,
and becomes amenable to moral disapprobation in the proper sense
of the term. If, for example, a man, through intemperance or extravagance,
becomes unable to pay his debts, or, having undertaken the moral
responsibility of a family, becomes from the same cause incapable
of supporting or educating them, he is deservedly reprobated,
and might be justly punished; but it is for the breach of duty
to his family or creditors, not for the extravagence. If the resources
which ought to have been devoted to them, had been diverted from
them for the most prudent investment, the moral culpability would
have been the same. George Barnwell murdered his uncle to get
money for his mistress, but if he had done it to set himself up
in business, he would equally have been hanged. Again, in the
frequent case of a man who causes grief to his family by addiction
to bad habits, he deserves reproach for his unkindness or ingratitude;
but so he may for cultivating habits not in themselves vicious,
if they are painful to those with whom he passes his life, or
who from personal ties are dependent on him for their comfort.
Whoever fails in the consideration generally due to the interests
and feelings of others, not being compelled by some more imperative
duty, or justified by allowable self-preference, is a subject
of moral disapprobation for that failure, but not for the cause
of it, nor for the errors, merely personal to himself, which may
have remotely led to it. In like manner, when a person disables
himself, by conduct purely self-regarding, from the performance
of some definite duty incumbent on him to the public, he is guilty
of a social offence. No person ought to be punished simply for
being drunk; but a soldier or a policeman should be punished for
being drunk on duty. Whenever, in short, there is a definite damage,
or a definite risk of damage, either to an individual or to the
public, the case is taken out of the province of liberty, and
placed in that of morality or law.
But with regard to the merely contingent or, as it may be called,
constructive injury which a person causes to society, by conduct
which neither violates any specific duty to the public, nor occasions
perceptible hurt to any assignable individual except himself;
the inconvenience is one which society can afford to bear, for
the sake of the greater good of human freedom. If grown persons
are to be punished for not taking proper care of themselves, I
would rather it were for their own sake, than under pretence of
preventing them from impairing their capacity of rendering to
society benefits which society does not pretend it has a right
to exact. But I cannot consent to argue the point as if society
had no means of bringing its weaker members up to its ordinary
standard of rational conduct, except waiting till they do something
irrational, and then punishing them, legally or morally, for it.
Society has had absolute power over them during all the early
portion of their existence: it has had the whole period of childhood
and nonage in which to try whether it could make them capable
of rational conduct in life. The existing generation is master
both of the training and the entire circumstances of the generation
to come; it cannot indeed make them perfectly wise and good, because
it is itself so lamentably deficient in goodness and wisdom; and
its best efforts are not always, in individual cases, its most
successful ones; but it is perfectly well able to make the rising
generation, as a whole, as good as, and a little better than,
itself. If society lets any considerable number of its members
grow up mere children, incapable of being acted on by rational
consideration of distant motives, society has itself to blame
for the consequences. Armed not only with all the powers of education,
but with the ascendency which the authority of a received opinion
always exercises over the minds who are least fitted to judge
for themselves; and aided by the natural penalties which cannot
be prevented from falling on those who incur the distaste or the
contempt of those who know them; let not society pretend that
it needs, besides all this, the power to issue commands and enforce
obedience in the personal concerns of individuals, in which, on
all principles of justice and policy, the decision ought to rest
with those who are to abide the consequences. Nor is there anything
which tends more to discredit and frustrate the better means of
influencing conduct, than a resort to the worse. If there be among
those whom it is attempted to coerce into prudence or temperance,
any of the material of which vigorous and independent characters
are made, they will infallibly rebel against the yoke. No such
person will ever feel that others have a right to control him
in his concerns, such as they have to prevent him from injuring
them in theirs; and it easily comes to be considered a mark of
spirit and courage to fly in the face of such usurped authority,
and do with ostentation the exact opposite of what it enjoins;
as in the fashion of grossness which succeeded, in the time of
Charles II., to the fanatical moral intolerance of the Puritans.
With respect to what is said of the necessity of protecting society
from the bad example set to others by the vicious or the self-indulgent;
it is true that bad example may have a pernicious effect, especially
the example of doing wrong to others with impunity to the wrong-doer.
But we are now speaking of conduct which, while it does no wrong
to others, is supposed to do great harm to the agent himself:
and I do not see how those who believe this, can think otherwise
than that the example, on the whole, must be more salutary than
hurtful, since, if it displays the misconduct, it displays also
the painful or degrading consequences which, if the conduct is
justly censured, must be supposed to be in all or most cases attendant
on it.
But the strongest of all the arguments against the interference
of the public with purely personal conduct, is that when it does
interfere, the odds are that it interferes wrongly, and in the
wrong place. On questions of social morality, of duty to others,
the opinion of the public, that is, of an overruling majority,
though often wrong, is likely to be still oftener right; because
on such questions they are only required to judge of their own
interests; of the manner in which some mode of conduct, if allowed
to be practised, would affect themselves. But the opinion of a
similar majority, imposed as a law on the minority, on questions
of self-regarding conduct, is quite as likely to be wrong as right;
for in these cases public opinion means, at the best, some people's
opinion of what is good or bad for other people; while very often
it does not even mean that; the public, with the most perfect
indifference, passing over the pleasure or convenience of those
whose conduct they censure, and considering only their own preference.
There are many who consider as an injury to themselves any conduct
which they have a distaste for, and resent it as an outrage to
their feelings; as a religious bigot, when charged with disregarding
the religious feelings of others, has been known to retort that
they disregard his feelings, by persisting in their abominable
worship or creed. But there is no parity between the feeling of
a person for his own opinion, and the feeling of another who is
offended at his holding it; no more than between the desire of
a thief to take a purse, and the desire of the right owner to
keep it. And a person's taste is as much his own peculiar concern
as his opinion or his purse. It is easy for any one to imagine
an ideal public, which leaves the freedom and choice of individuals
in all uncertain matters undisturbed, and only requires them to
abstain from modes of conduct which universal experience has condemned.
But where has there been seen a public which set any such limit
to its censorship? or when does the public trouble itself about
universal experience. In its interferences with personal conduct
it is seldom thinking of anything but the enormity of acting or
feeling differently from itself; and this standard of judgment,
thinly disguised, is held up to mankind as the dictate of religion
and philosophy, by nine tenths of all moralists and speculative
writers. These teach that things are right because they are right;
because we feel them to be so. They tell us to search in our own
minds and hearts for laws of conduct binding on ourselves and
on all others. What can the poor public do but apply these instructions,
and make their own personal feelings of good and evil, if they
are tolerably unanimous in them, obligatory on all the world?
The evil here pointed out is not one which exists only in theory;
and it may perhaps be expected that I should specify the instances
in which the public of this age and country improperly invests
its own preferences with the character of moral laws. I am not
writing an essay on the aberrations of existing moral feeling.
That is too weighty a subject to be discussed parenthetically,
and by way of illustration. Yet examples are necessary, to show
that the principle I maintain is of serious and practical moment,
and that I am not endeavoring to erect a barrier against imaginary
evils. And it is not difficult to show, by abundant instances,
that to extend the bounds of what may be called moral police,
until it encroaches on the most unquestionably legitimate liberty
of the individual, is one of the most universal of all human propensities.
As a first instance, consider the antipathies which men cherish
on no better grounds than that persons whose religious opinions
are different from theirs, do not practise their religious observances,
especially their religious abstinences. To cite a rather trivial
example, nothing in the creed or practice of Christians does more
to envenom the hatred of Mahomedans against them, than the fact
of their eating pork. There are few acts which Christians and
Europeans regard with more unaffected disgust, than Mussulmans
regard this particular mode of satisfying hunger. It is, in the
first place, an offence against their religion; but this circumstance
by no means explains either the degree or the kind of their repugnance;
for wine also is forbidden by their religion, and to partake of
it is by all Mussulmans accounted wrong, but not disgusting. Their
aversion to the flesh of the "unclean beast" is, on
the contrary, of that peculiar character, resembling an instinctive
antipathy, which the idea of uncleanness, when once it thoroughly
sinks into the feelings, seems always to excite even in those
whose personal habits are anything but scrupulously cleanly and
of which the sentiment of religious impurity, so intense in the
Hindoos, is a remarkable example. Suppose now that in a people,
of whom the majority were Mussulmans, that majority should insist
upon not permitting pork to be eaten within the limits of the
country. This would be nothing new in Mahomedan countries.[1]
Would it be a legitimate exercise of the moral authority of public
opinion? and if not, why not? The practice is really revolting
to such a public. They also sincerely think that it is forbidden
and abhorred by the Deity. Neither could the prohibition be censured
as religious persecution. It might be religious in its origin,
but it would not be persecution for religion, since nobody's religion
makes it a duty to eat pork. The only tenable ground of condemnation
would be, that with the personal tastes and self-regarding concerns
of individuals the public has no business to interfere.
To come somewhat nearer home: the majority of Spaniards consider
it a gross impiety, offensive in the highest degree to the Supreme
Being, to worship him in any other manner than the Roman Catholic;
and no other public worship is lawful on Spanish soil. The people
of all Southern Europe look upon a married clergy as not only
irreligious, but unchaste, indecent, gross, disgusting. What do
Protestants think of these perfectly sincere feelings, and of
the attempt to enforce them against non-Catholics? Yet, if mankind
are justified in interfering with each other's liberty in things
which do not concern the interests of others, on what principle
is it possible consistently to exclude these cases? or who can
blame people for desiring to suppress what they regard as a scandal
in the sight of God and man?
No stronger case can be shown for prohibiting anything which is
regarded as a personal immorality, than is made out for suppressing
these practices in the eyes of those who regard them as impieties;
and unless we are willing to adopt the logic of persecutors, and
to say that we may persecute others because we are right, and
that they must not persecute us because they are wrong, we must
beware of admitting a principle of which we should resent as a
gross injustice the application to ourselves.
The preceding instances may be objected to, although unreasonably,
as drawn from contingencies impossible among us: opinion, in this
country, not being likely to enforce abstinence from meats, or
to interfere with people for worshipping, and for either marrying
or not marrying, according to their creed or inclination. The
next example, however, shall be taken from an interference with
liberty which we have by no means passed all danger of. Wherever
the Puritans have been sufficiently powerful, as in New England,
and in Great Britain at the time of the Commonwealth, they have
endeavored, with considerable success, to put down all public,
and nearly all private, amusements: especially music, dancing,
public games, or other assemblages for purposes of diversion,
and the theatre. There are still in this country large bodies
of persons by whose notions of morality and religion these recreations
are condemned; and those persons belonging chiefly to the middle
class, who are the ascendant power in the present social and political
condition of the kingdom, it is by no means impossible that persons
of these sentiments may at some time or other command a majority
in Parliament. How will the remaining portion of the community
like to have the amusements that shall be permitted to them regulated
by the religious and moral sentiments of the stricter Calvinists
and Methodists? Would they not, with considerable peremptoriness,
desire these intrusively pious members of society to mind their
own business? This is precisely what should be said to every government
and every public, who have the pretension that no person shall
enjoy any pleasure which they think wrong. But if the principle
of the pretension be admitted, no one can reasonably object to
its being acted on in the sense of the majority, or other preponderating
power in the country; and all persons must be ready to conform
to the idea of a Christian commonwealth, as understood by the
early settlers in New England, if a religious profession similar
to theirs should ever succeed in regaining its lost ground, as
religions supposed to be declining have so often been known to
do.
To imagine another contingency, perhaps more likely to be realized
than the one last mentioned. There is confessedly a strong tendency
in the modern world towards a democratic constitution of society,
accompanied or not by popular political institutions. It is affirmed
that in the country where this tendency is most completely realized--where
both society and the government are most democratic--the United
States--the feeling of the majority, to whom any appearance of
a more showy or costly style of living than they can hope to rival
is disagreeable, operates as a tolerably effectual sumptuary law,
and that in many parts of the Union it is really difficult for
a person possessing a very large income, to find any mode of spending
it, which will not incur popular disapprobation. Though such statements
as these are doubtless much exaggerated as a representation of
existing facts, the state of things they describe is not only
a conceivable and possible, but a probable result of democratic
feeling, combined with the notion that the public has a right
to a veto on the manner in which individuals shall spend their
incomes. We have only further to suppose a considerable diffusion
of Socialist opinions, and it may become infamous in the eyes
of the majority to possess more property than some very small
amount, or any income not earned by manual labor. Opinions similar
in principle to these, already prevail widely among the artisan
class, and weigh oppressively on those who are amenable to the
opinion chiefly of that class, namely, its own members. It is
known that the bad workmen who form the majority of the operatives
in many branches of industry, are decidedly of opinion that bad
workmen ought to receive the same wages as good, and that no one
ought to be allowed, through piecework or otherwise, to earn by
superior skill or industry more than others can without it. And
they employ a moral police, which occasionally becomes a physical
one, to deter skilful workmen from receiving, and employers from
giving, a larger remuneration for a more useful service. If the
public have any jurisdiction over private concerns, I cannot see
that these people are in fault, or that any individual's particular
public can be blamed for asserting the same authority over his
individual conduct, which the general public asserts over people
in general.
But, without dwelling upon supposititious cases, there are, in
our own day, gross usurpations upon the liberty of private life
actually practised, and still greater ones threatened with some
expectation of success, and opinions proposed which assert an
unlimited right in the public not only to prohibit by law everything
which it thinks wrong, but in order to get at what it thinks wrong,
to prohibit any number of things which it admits to be innocent.
Under the name of preventing intemperance the people of one English
colony, and of nearly half the United States, have been interdicted
by law from making any use whatever of fermented drinks, except
for medical purposes: for prohibition of their sale is in fact,
as it is intended to be, prohibition of their use. And though
the impracticability of executing the law has caused its repeal
in several of the States which had adopted it, including the one
from which it derives its name, an attempt has notwithstanding
been commenced, and is prosecuted with considerable zeal by many
of the professed philanthropists, to agitate for a similar law
in this country. The association, or "Alliance" as it
terms itself, which has been formed for this purpose, has acquired
some notoriety through the publicity given to a correspondence
between its Secretary and one of the very few English public men
who hold that a politician's opinions ought to be founded on principles.
Lord Stanley's share in this correspondence is calculated to strengthen
the hopes already built on him, by those who know how rare such
qualities as are manifested in some of his public appearances,
unhappily are among those who figure in political life. The organ
of the Alliance, who would "deeply deplore the recognition
of any principle which could be wrested to justify bigotry and
persecution," undertakes to point out the "broad and
impassable barrier" which divides such principles from those
of the association. "All matters relating to thought, opinion,
conscience, appear to me," he says, "to be without the
sphere of legislation; all pertaining to social act, habit, relation,
subject only to a discretionary power vested in the State itself,
and not in the individual, to be within it." No mention is
made of a third class, different from either of these, viz., acts
and habits which are not social, but individual; although it is
to this class, surely, that the act of drinking fermented liquors
belongs. Selling fermented liquors, however, is trading, and trading
is a social act. But the infringement complained of is not on
the liberty of the seller, but on that of the buyer and consumer;
since the State might just as well forbid him to drink wine, as
purposely make it impossible for him to obtain it. The Secretary,
however, says, "I claim, as a citizen, a right to legislate
whenever my social rights are invaded by the social act of another."
And now for the definition of these "social rights."
"If anything invades my social rights, certainly the traffic
in strong drink does. It destroys my primary right of security,
by constantly creating and stimulating social disorder. It invades
my right of equality, by deriving a profit from the creation of
a misery, I am taxed to support. It impedes my right to free moral
and intellectual development, by surrounding my path with dangers,
and by weakening and demoralizing society, from which I have a
right to claim mutual aid and intercourse." A theory of "social
rights," the like of which probably never before found its
way into distinct language--being nothing short of this--that
it is the absolute social right of every individual, that every
other individual shall act in every respect exactly as he ought;
that whosoever fails thereof in the smallest particular, violates
my social right, and entitles me to demand from the legislature
the removal of the grievance. So monstrous a principle is far
more dangerous than any single interference with liberty; there
is no violation of liberty which it would not justify; it acknowledges
no right to any freedom whatever, except perhaps to that of holding
opinions in secret, without ever disclosing them; for the moment
an opinion which I consider noxious, passes any one's lips, it
invades all the "social rights" attributed to me by
the Alliance. The doctrine ascribes to all mankind a vested interest
in each other's moral, intellectual, and even physical perfection,
to be defined by each claimant according to his own standard.
Another important example of illegitimate interference with the
rightful liberty of the individual, not simply threatened, but
long since carried into triumphant effect, is Sabbatarian legislation.
Without doubt, abstinence on one day in the week, so far as the
exigencies of life permit, from the usual daily occupation, though
in no respect religiously binding on any except Jews, is a highly
beneficial custom. And inasmuch as this custom cannot be observed
without a general consent to that effect among the industrious
classes, therefore, in so far as some persons by working may impose
the same necessity on others, it may be allowable and right that
the law should guarantee to each, the observance by others of
the custom, by suspending the greater operations of industry on
a particular day. But this justification, grounded on the direct
interest which others have in each individual's observance of
the practice, does not apply to the self-chosen occupations in
which a person may think fit to employ his leisure; nor does it
hold good, in the smallest degree, for legal restrictions on amusements.
It is true that the amusement of some is the day's work of others;
but the pleasure, not to say the useful recreation, of many, is
worth the labor of a few, provided the occupation is freely chosen,
and can be freely resigned. The operatives are perfectly right
in thinking that if all worked on Sunday, seven days' work would
have to be given for six days' wages: but so long as the great
mass of employments are suspended, the small number who for the
enjoyment of others must still work, obtain a proportional increase
of earnings; and they are not obliged to follow those occupations,
if they prefer leisure to emolument. If a further remedy is sought,
it might be found in the establishment by custom of a holiday
on some other day of the week for those particular classes of
persons. The only ground, therefore, on which restrictions on
Sunday amusements can be defended, must be that they are religiously
wrong; a motive of legislation which never can be too earnestly
protested against. "Deorum injuriae Diis curae." It
remains to be proved that society or any of its officers holds
a commission from on high to avenge any supposed offence to Omnipotence,
which is not also a wrong to our fellow-creatures. The notion
that it is one man's duty that another should be religious, was
the foundation of all the religious persecutions ever perpetrated,
and if admitted, would fully justify them. Though the feeling
which breaks out in the repeated attempts to stop railway travelling
on Sunday, in the resistance to the opening of Museums, and the
like, has not the cruelty of the old persecutors, the state of
mind indicated by it is fundamentally the same. It IS a determination
not to tolerate others in doing what is permitted by their religion,
because it is not permitted by the persecutor's religion. It is
a belief that God not only abominates the act of the misbeliever,
but will not hold us guiltless if we leave him unmolested.
I cannot refrain from adding to these examples of the little account
commonly made of human liberty, the language of downright persecution
which breaks out from the press of this country, whenever it feels
called on to notice the remarkable phenomenon of Mormonism. Much
might be said on the unexpected and instructive fact, that an
alleged new revelation, and a religion, founded on it, the product
of palpable imposture, not even supported by the prestige of extraordinary
qualities in its founder, is believed by hundreds of thousands,
and has been made the foundation of a society, in the age of newspapers,
railways, and the electric telegraph. What here concerns us is,
that this religion, like other and better religions, has its martyrs;
that its prophet and founder was, for his teaching, put to death
by a mob; that others of its adherents lost their lives by the
same lawless violence; that they were forcibly expelled, in a
body, from the country in which they first grew up; while, now
that they have been chased into a solitary recess in the midst
of a desert, many in this country openly declare that it would
be right (only that it is not convenient) to send an expedition
against them, and compel them by force to conform to the opinions
of other people. The article of the Mormonite doctrine which is
the chief provocative to the antipathy which thus breaks through
the ordinary restraints of religious tolerance, is its sanction
of polygamy; which, though permitted to Mahomedans, and Hindoos,
and Chinese, seems to excite unquenchable animosity when practised
by persons who speak English, and profess to be a kind of Christians.
No one has a deeper disapprobation than I have of this Mormon
institution; both for other reasons, and because, far from being
in any way countenanced by the principle of liberty, it is a direct
infraction of that principle, being a mere riveting of the chains
of one half of the community, and an emancipation of the other
from reciprocity of obligation towards them. Still, it must be
remembered that this relation is as much voluntary on the part
of the women concerned in it, and who may be deemed the sufferers
by it, as is the case with any other form of the marriage institution;
and however surprising this fact may appear, it has its explanation
in the common ideas and customs of the world, which teaching women
to think marriage the one thing needful, make it intelligible
that many a woman should prefer being one of several wives, to
not being a wife at all. Other countries are not asked to recognize
such unions, or release any portion of their inhabitants from
their own laws on the score of Mormonite opinions. But when the
dissentients have conceded to the hostile sentiments of others,
far more than could justly be demanded; when they have left the
countries to which their doctrines were unacceptable, and established
themselves in a remote corner of the earth, which they have been
the first to render habitable to human beings; it is difficult
to see on what principles but those of tyranny they can be prevented
from living there under what laws they please, provided they commit
no aggression on other nations, and allow perfect freedom of departure
to those who are dissatisfied with their ways. A recent writer,
in some respects of considerable merit, proposes (to use his own
words,) not a crusade, but a civilizade, against this polygamous
community, to put an end to what seems to him a retrograde step
in civilization. It also appears so to me, but I am not aware
that any community has a right to force another to be civilized.
So long as the sufferers by the bad law do not invoke assistance
from other communities, I cannot admit that persons entirely unconnected
with them ought to step in and require that a condition of things
with which all who are directly interested appear to be satisfied,
should be put an end to because it is a scandal to persons some
thousands of miles distant, who have no part or concern in it.
Let them send missionaries, if they please, to preach against
it; and let them, by any fair means, (of which silencing the teachers
is not one,) oppose the progress of similar doctrines among their
own people. If civilization has got the better of barbarism when
barbarism had the world to itself, it is too much to profess to
be afraid lest barbarism, after having been fairly got under,
should revive and conquer civilization. A civilization that can
thus succumb to its vanquished enemy must first have become so
degenerate, that neither its appointed priests and teachers, nor
anybody else, has the capacity, or will take the trouble, to stand
up for it. If this be so, the sooner such a civilization receives
notice to quit, the better. It can only go on from bad to worse,
until destroyed and regenerated (like the Western Empire) by energetic
barbarians. [1] The case of the Bombay Parsees is a curious instance
in point. When this industrious and enterprising tribe, the descendants
of the Persian fireworshippers, flying from their native country
before the Caliphs, arrived in Western India, they were admitted
to toleration by the Hindoo sovereigns, on condition of not eating
beef. When those regions afterwards fell under the dominion of
Mahomedan conquerors, the Parsees obtained from them a continuance
of indulgence, on condition of refraining from pork. What was
at first obedience to authority became a second nature, and the
Parsees to this day abstain both from beef and pork. Though not
required by their religion, the double abstinence has had time
to grow into a custom of their tribe; and custom, in the East,
is a religion.
CHAPTER V APPLICATIONS
THE principles asserted in these pages must be more generally
admitted as the basis for discussion of details, before a consistent
application of them to all the various departments of government
and morals can be attempted with any prospect of advantage. The
few observations I propose to make on questions of detail, are
designed to illustrate the principles, rather than to follow them
out to their consequences. I offer, not so much applications,
as specimens of application; which may serve to bring into greater
clearness the meaning and limits of the two maxims which together
form the entire doctrine of this Essay and to assist the judgment
in holding the balance between them, in the cases where it appears
doubtful which of them is applicable to the case.
The maxims are, first, that the individual is not accountable
to society for his actions, in so far as these concern the interests
of no person but himself. Advice, instruction, persuasion, and
avoidance by other people, if thought necessary by them for their
own good, are the only measures by which society can justifiably
express its dislike or disapprobation of his conduct. Secondly,
that for such actions as are prejudicial to the interests of others,
the individual is accountable, and may be subjected either to
social or to legal punishments, if society is of opinion that
the one or the other is requisite for its protection.
In the first place, it must by no means be supposed, because damage,
or probability of damage, to the interests of others, can alone
justify the interference of society, that therefore it always
does justify such interference. In many cases, an individual,
in pursuing a legitimate object, necessarily and therefore legitimately
causes pain or loss to others, or intercepts a good which they
had a reasonable hope of obtaining. Such oppositions of interest
between individuals often arise from bad social institutions,
but are unavoidable while those institutions last; and some would
be unavoidable under any institutions. Whoever succeeds in an
overcrowded profession, or in a competitive examination; whoever
is preferred to another in any contest for an object which both
desire, reaps benefit from the loss of others, from their wasted
exertion and their disappointment. But it is, by common admission,
better for the general interest of mankind, that persons should
pursue their objects undeterred by this sort of consequences.
In other words, society admits no right, either legal or moral,
in the disappointed competitors, to immunity from this kind of
suffering; and feels called on to interfere, only when means of
success have been employed which it is contrary to the general
interest to permit--namely, fraud or treachery, and force.
Again, trade is a social act. Whoever undertakes to sell any description
of goods to the public, does what affects the interest of other
persons, and of society in general; and thus his conduct, in principle,
comes within the jurisdiction of society: accordingly, it was
once held to be the duty of governments, in all cases which were
considered of importance, to fix prices, and regulate the processes
of manufacture. But it is now recognized, though not till after
a long struggle, that both the cheapness and the good quality
of commodities are most effectually provided for by leaving the
producers and sellers perfectly free, under the sole check of
equal freedom to the buyers for supplying themselves elsewhere.
This is the so-called doctrine of Free Trade, which rests on grounds
different from, though equally solid with, the principle of individual
liberty asserted in this Essay. Restrictions on trade, or on production
for purposes of trade, are indeed restraints; and all restraint,
qua restraint, is an evil: but the restraints in question affect
only that part of conduct which society is competent to restrain,
and are wrong solely because they do not really produce the results
which it is desired to produce by them. As the principle of individual
liberty is not involved in the doctrine of Free Trade so neither
is it in most of the questions which arise respecting the limits
of that doctrine: as for example, what amount of public control
is admissible for the prevention of fraud by adulteration; how
far sanitary precautions, or arrangements to protect work-people
employed in dangerous occupations, should be enforced on employers.
Such questions involve considerations of liberty, only in so far
as leaving people to themselves is always better, caeteris paribus,
than controlling them: but that they may be legitimately controlled
for these ends, is in principle undeniable. On the other hand,
there are questions relating to interference with trade which
are essentially questions of liberty; such as the Maine Law, already
touched upon; the prohibition of the importation of opium into
China; the restriction of the sale of poisons; all cases, in short,
where the object of the interference is to make it impossible
or difficult to obtain a particular commodity. These interferences
are objectionable, not as infringements on the liberty of the
producer or seller, but on that of the buyer.
One of these examples, that of the sale of poisons, opens a new
question; the proper limits of what may be called the functions
of police; how far liberty may legitimately be invaded for the
prevention of crime, or of accident. It is one of the undisputed
functions of government to take precautions against crime before
it has been committed, as well as to detect and punish it afterwards.
The preventive function of government, however, is far more liable
to be abused, to the prejudice of liberty, than the punitory function;
for there is hardly any part of the legitimate freedom of action
of a human being which would not admit of being represented, and
fairly too, as increasing the facilities for some form or other
of delinquency. Nevertheless, if a public authority, or even a
private person, sees any one evidently preparing to commit a crime,
they are not bound to look on inactive until the crime is committed,
but may interfere to prevent it. If poisons were never bought
or used for any purpose except the commission of murder, it would
be right to prohibit their manufacture and sale. They may, however,
be wanted not only for innocent but for useful purposes, and restrictions
cannot be imposed in the one case without operating in the other.
Again, it is a proper office of public authority to guard against
accidents. If either a public officer or any one else saw a person
attempting to cross a bridge which had been ascertained to be
unsafe, and there were no time to warn him of his danger, they
might seize him and turn him back without any real infringement
of his liberty; for liberty consists in doing what one desires,
and he does not desire to fall into the river. Nevertheless, when
there is not a certainty, but only a danger of mischief, no one
but the person himself can judge of the sufficiency of the motive
which may prompt him to incur the risk: in this case, therefore,
(unless he is a child, or delirious, or in some state of excitement
or absorption incompatible with the full use of the reflecting
faculty,) he ought, I conceive, to be only warned of the danger;
not forcibly prevented from exposing himself to it. Similar considerations,
applied to such a question as the sale of poisons, may enable
us to decide which among the possible modes of regulation are
or are not contrary to principle. Such a precaution, for example,
as that of labelling the drug with some word expressive of its
dangerous character, may be enforced without violation of liberty:
the buyer cannot wish not to know that the thing he possesses
has poisonous qualities. But to require in all cases the certificate
of a medical practitioner, would make it sometimes impossible,
always expensive, to obtain the article for legitimate uses. The
only mode apparent to me, in which difficulties may be thrown
in the way of crime committed through this means, without any
infringement, worth taking into account, Upon the liberty of those
who desire the poisonous substance for other purposes, consists
in providing what, in the apt language of Bentham, is called "preappointed
evidence." This provision is familiar to every one in the
case of contracts. It is usual and right that the law, when a
contract is entered into, should require as the condition of its
enforcing performance, that certain formalities should be observed,
such as signatures, attestation of witnesses, and the like, in
order that in case of subsequent dispute, there may be evidence
to prove that the contract was really entered into, and that there
was nothing in the circumstances to render it legally invalid:
the effect being, to throw great obstacles in the way of fictitious
contracts, or contracts made in circumstances which, if known,
would destroy their validity. Precautions of a similar nature
might be enforced in the sale of articles adapted to be instruments
of crime. The seller, for example, might be required to enter
in a register the exact time of the transaction, the name and
address of the buyer, the precise quality and quantity sold; to
ask the purpose for which it was wanted, and record the answer
he received. When there was no medical prescription, the presence
of some third person might be required, to bring home the fact
to the purchaser, in case there should afterwards be reason to
believe that the article had been applied to criminal purposes.
Such regulations would in general be no material impediment to
obtaining the article, but a very considerable one to making an
improper use of it without detection.
The right inherent in society, to ward off crimes against itself
by antecedent precautions, suggests the obvious limitations to
the maxim, that purely self-regarding misconduct cannot properly
be meddled with in the way of prevention or punishment. Drunkennesses,
for example, in ordinary cases, is not a fit subject for legislative
interference; but I should deem it perfectly legitimate that a
person, who had once been convicted of any act of violence to
others under the influence of drink, should be placed under a
special legal restriction, personal to himself; that if he were
afterwards found drunk, he should be liable to a penalty, and
that if when in that state he committed another offence, the punishment
to which he would be liable for that other offence should be increased
in severity. The making himself drunk, in a person whom drunkenness
excites to do harm to others, is a crime against others. So, again,
idleness, except in a person receiving support from the public,
or except when it constitutes a breach of contract, cannot without
tyranny be made a subject of legal punishment; but if either from
idleness or from any other avoidable cause, a man fails to perform
his legal duties to others, as for instance to support his children,
it is no tyranny to force him to fulfil that obligation, by compulsory
labor, if no other means are available.
Again, there are many acts which, being directly injurious only
to the agents themselves, ought not to be legally interdicted,
but which, if done publicly, are a violation of good manners,
and coming thus within the category of offences against others,
may rightfully be prohibited. Of this kind are offences against
decency; on which it is unnecessary to dwell, the rather as they
are only connected indirectly with our subject, the objection
to publicity being equally strong in the case of many actions
not in themselves condemnable, nor supposed to be so.
There is another question to which an answer must be found, consistent
with the principles which have been laid down. In cases of personal
conduct supposed to be blameable, but which respect for liberty
precludes society from preventing or punishing, because the evil
directly resulting falls wholly on the agent; what the agent is
free to do, ought other persons to be equally free to counsel
or instigate? This question is not free from difficulty. The case
of a person who solicits another to do an act, is not strictly
a case of self-regarding conduct. To give advice or offer inducements
to any one, is a social act, and may therefore, like actions in
general which affect others, be supposed amenable to social control.
But a little reflection corrects the first impression, by showing
that if the case is not strictly within the definition of individual
liberty, yet the reasons on which the principle of individual
liberty is grounded, are applicable to it. If people must be allowed,
in whatever concerns only themselves, to act as seems best to
themselves at their own peril, they must equally be free to consult
with one another about what is fit to be so done; to exchange
opinions, and give and receive suggestions. Whatever it is permitted
to do, it must be permitted to advise to do. The question is doubtful,
only when the instigator derives a personal benefit from his advice;
when he makes it his occupation, for subsistence, or pecuniary
gain, to promote what society and the State consider to be an
evil. Then, indeed, a new element of complication is introduced;
namely, the existence of classes of persons with an interest opposed
to what is considered as the public weal, and whose mode of living
is grounded on the counteraction of it. Ought this to be interfered
with, or not? Fornication, for example, must be tolerated, and
so must gambling; but should a person be free to be a pimp, or
to keep a gambling-house? The case is one of those which lie on
the exact boundary line between two principles, and it is not
at once apparent to which of the two it properly belongs. There
are arguments on both sides. On the side of toleration it may
be said, that the fact of following anything as an occupation,
and living or profiting by the practice of it, cannot make that
criminal which would otherwise be admissible; that the act should
either be consistently permitted or consistently prohibited; that
if the principles which we have hitherto defended are true, society
has no business, as society, to decide anything to be wrong which
concerns only the individual; that it cannot go beyond dissuasion,
and that one person should be as free to persuade, as another
to dissuade. In opposition to this it may be contended, that although
the public, or the State, are not warranted in authoritatively
deciding, for purposes of repression or punishment, that such
or such conduct affecting only the interests of the individual
is good or bad, they are fully justified in assuming, if they
regard it as bad, that its being so or not is at least a disputable
question: That, this being supposed, they cannot be acting wrongly
in endeavoring to exclude the influence of solicitations which
are not disinterested, of instigators who cannot possibly be impartial--who
have a direct personal interest on one side, and that side the
one which the State believes to be wrong, and who confessedly
promote it for personal objects only. There can surely, it may
be urged, be nothing lost, no sacrifice of good, by so ordering
matters that persons shall make their election, either wisely
or foolishly, on their own prompting, as free as possible from
the arts of persons who stimulate their inclinations for interested
purposes of their own. Thus (it may be said) though the statutes
respecting unlawful games are utterly indefensible--though all
persons should be free to gamble in their own or each other's
houses, or in any place of meeting established by their own subscriptions,
and open only to the members and their visitors--yet public gambling-houses
should not be permitted. It is true that the prohibition is never
effectual, and that whatever amount of tyrannical power is given
to the police, gamblinghouses can always be maintained under other
pretences; but they may be compelled to conduct their operations
with a certain degree of secrecy and mystery, so that nobody knows
anything about them but those who seek them; and more than this
society ought not to aim at. There is considerable force in these
arguments. I will not venture to decide whether they are sufficient
to justify the moral anomaly of punishing the accessary, when
the principal is (and must be) allowed to go free; of fining or
imprisoning the procurer, but not the fornicator, the gambling-house
keeper, but not the gambler. Still less ought the common operations
of buying and selling to be interfered with on analogous grounds.
Almost every article which is bought and sold may be used in excess,
and the sellers have a pecuniary interest in encouraging that
excess; but no argument can be founded on this, in favor, for
instance, of the Maine Law; because the class of dealers in strong
drinks, though interested in their abuse, are indispensably required
for the sake of their legitimate use. The interest, however, of
these dealers in promoting intemperance is a real evil, and justifies
the State in imposing restrictions and requiring guarantees, which
but for that justification would be infringements of legitimate
liberty.
A further question is, whether the State while it permits, should
nevertheless indirectly discourage conduct which it deems contrary
to the best interests of the agent; whether, for example, it should
take measures to render the means of drunkenness more costly,
or add to the difficulty of procuring them, by limiting the number
of the places of sale. On this as on most other practical questions,
many distinctions require to be made. To tax stimulants for the
sole purpose of making them more difficult to be obtained, is
a measure differing only in degree from their entire prohibition;
and would be justifiable only if that were justifiable. Every
increase of cost is a prohibition, to those whose means do not
come up to the augmented price; and to those who do, it is a penalty
laid on them for gratifying a particular taste. Their choice of
pleasures, and their mode of expending their income, after satisfying
their legal and moral obligations to the State and to individuals,
are their own concern, and must rest with their own judgment.
These considerations may seem at first sight to condemn the selection
of stimulants as special subjects of taxation for purposes of
revenue. But it must be remembered that taxation for fiscal purposes
is absolutely inevitable; that in most countries it is necessary
that a considerable part of that taxation should be indirect;
that the State, therefore, cannot help imposing penalties, which
to some persons may be prohibitory, on the use of some articles
of consumption. It is hence the duty of the State to consider,
in the imposition of taxes, what commodities the consumers can
best spare; and a fortiori, to select in preference those of which
it deems the use, beyond a very moderate quantity, to be positively
injurious. Taxation, therefore, of stimulants, up to the point
which produces the largest amount of revenue (supposing that the
State needs all the revenue which it yields) is not only admissible,
but to be approved of.
The question of making the sale of these commodities a more or
less exclusive privilege, must be answered differently, according
to the purposes to which the restriction is intended to be subservient.
All places of public resort require the restraint of a police,
and places of this kind peculiarly, because offences against society
are especially apt to originate there. It is, therefore, fit to
confine the power of selling these commodities (at least for consumption
on the spot) to persons of known or vouched-for respectability
of conduct; to make such regulations respecting hours of opening
and closing as may be requisite for public surveillance, and to
withdraw the license if breaches of the peace repeatedly take
place through the connivance or incapacity of the keeper of the
house, or if it becomes a rendezvous for concocting and preparing
offences against the law. Any further restriction I do not conceive
to be, in principle, justifiable. The limitation in number, for
instance, of beer and spirit-houses, for the express purpose of
rendering them more difficult of access, and diminishing the occasions
of temptation, not only exposes all to an inconvenience because
there are some by whom the facility would be abused, but is suited
only to a state of society in which the laboring classes are avowedly
treated as children or savages, and placed under an education
of restraint, to fit them for future admission to the privileges
of freedom. This is not the principle on which the laboring classes
are professedly governed in any free country; and no person who
sets due value on freedom will give his adhesion to their being
so governed, unless after all efforts have been exhausted to educate
them for freedom and govern them as freemen, and it has been definitively
proved that they can only be governed as children. The bare statement
of the alternative shows the absurdity of supposing that such
efforts have been made in any case which needs be considered here.
It is only because the institutions of this country are a mass
of inconsistencies, that things find admittance into our practice
which belong to the system of despotic, or what is called paternal,
government, while the general freedom of our institutions precludes
the exercise of the amount of control necessary to render the
restraint of any real efficacy as a moral education.
It was pointed out in an early part of this Essay, that the liberty
of the individual, in things wherein the individual is alone concerned,
implies a corresponding liberty in any number of individuals to
regulate by mutual agreement such things as regard them jointly,
and regard no persons but themselves. This question presents no
difficulty, so long as the will of all the persons implicated
remains unaltered; but since that will may change, it is often
necessary, even in things in which they alone are concerned, that
they should enter into engagements with one another; and when
they do, it is fit, as a general rule, that those engagements
should be kept. Yet in the laws probably, of every country, this
general rule has some exceptions. Not only persons are not held
to engagements which violate the rights of third parties, but
it is sometimes considered a sufficient reason for releasing them
from an engagement, that it is injurious to themselves. In this
and most other civilized countries, for example, an engagement
by which a person should sell himself, or allow himself to be
sold, as a slave, would be null and void; neither enforced by
law nor by opinion. The ground for thus limiting his power of
voluntarily disposing of his own lot in life, is apparent, and
is very clearly seen in this extreme case. The reason for not
interfering, unless for the sake of others, with a person's voluntary
acts, is consideration for his liberty. His voluntary choice is
evidence that what he so chooses is desirable, or at the least
endurable, to him, and his good is on the whole best provided
for by allowing him to take his own means of pursuing it. But
by selling himself for a slave, he abdicates his liberty; he foregoes
any future use of it, beyond that single act. He therefore defeats,
in his own case, the very purpose which is the justification of
allowing him to dispose of himself. He is no longer free; but
is thenceforth in a position which has no longer the presumption
in its favor, that would be afforded by his voluntarily remaining
in it. The principle of freedom cannot require that he should
be free not to be free. It is not freedom, to be allowed to alienate
his freedom. These reasons, the force of which is so conspicuous
in this peculiar case, are evidently of far wider application;
yet a limit is everywhere set to them by the necessities of life,
which continually require, not indeed that we should resign our
freedom, but that we should consent to this and the other limitation
of it. The principle, however, which demands uncontrolled freedom
of action in all that concerns only the agents themselves, requires
that those who have become bound to one another, in things which
concern no third party, should be able to release one another
from the engagement: and even without such voluntary release,
there are perhaps no contracts or engagements, except those that
relate to money or money's worth, of which one can venture to
say that there ought to be no liberty whatever of retractation.
Baron Wilhelm von Humboldt, in the excellent Essay from which
I have already quoted, states it as his conviction, that engagements
which involve personal relations or services, should never be
legally binding beyond a limited duration of time; and that the
most important of these engagements, marriage, having the peculiarity
that its objects are frustrated unless the feelings of both the
parties are in harmony with it, should require nothing more than
the declared will of either party to dissolve it. This subject
is too important, and too complicated, to be discussed in a parenthesis,
and I touch on it only so far as is necessary for purposes of
illustration. If the conciseness and generality of Baron Humboldt's
dissertation had not obliged him in this instance to content himself
with enunciating his conclusion without discussing the premises,
he would doubtless have recognized that the question cannot be
decided on grounds so simple as those to which he confines himself.
When a person, either by express promise or by conduct, has encouraged
another to rely upon his continuing to act in a certain way--to
build expectations and calculations, and stake any part of his
plan of life upon that supposition, a new series of moral obligations
arises on his part towards that person, which may possibly be
overruled, but can not be ignored. And again, if the relation
between two contracting parties has been followed by consequences
to others; if it has placed third parties in any peculiar position,
or, as in the case of marriage, has even called third parties
into existence, obligations arise on the part of both the contracting
parties towards those third persons, the fulfilment of which,
or at all events, the mode of fulfilment, must be greatly affected
by the continuance or disruption of the relation between the original
parties to the contract. It does not follow, nor can I admit,
that these obligations extend to requiring the fulfilment of the
contract at all costs to the happiness of the reluctant party;
but they are a necessary element in the question; and even if,
as Von Humboldt maintains, they ought to make no difference in
the legal freedom of the parties to release themselves from the
engagement (and I also hold that they ought not to make much difference),
they necessarily make a great difference in the moral freedom.
A person is bound to take all these circumstances into account,
before resolving on a step which may affect such important interests
of others; and if he does not allow proper weight to those interests,
he is morally responsible for the wrong. I have made these obvious
remarks for the better illustration of the general principle of
liberty, and not because they are at all needed on the particular
question, which, on the contrary, is usually discussed as if the
interest of children was everything, and that of grown persons
nothing.
I have already observed that, owing to the absence of any recognized
general principles, liberty is often granted where it should be
withheld, as well as withheld where it should be granted; and
one of the cases in which, in the modern European world, the sentiment
of liberty is the strongest, is a case where, in my view, it is
altogether misplaced. A person should be free to do as he likes
in his own concerns; but he ought not to be free to do as he likes
in acting for another under the pretext that the affairs of another
are his own affairs. The State, while it respects the liberty
of each in what specially regards himself, is bound to maintain
a vigilant control over his exercise of any power which it allows
him to possess over others. This obligation is almost entirely
disregarded in the case of the family relations, a case, in its
direct influence on human happiness, more important than all the
others taken together. The almost despotic power of husbands over
wives needs not be enlarged upon here, because nothing more is
needed for the complete removal of the evil, than that wives should
have the same rights, and should receive the protection of law
in the same manner, as all other persons; and because, on this
subject, the defenders of established injustice do not avail themselves
of the plea of liberty, but stand forth openly as the champions
of power. It is in the case of children, that misapplied notions
of liberty are a real obstacle to the fulfilment by the State
of its duties. One would almost think that a man's children were
supposed to be literally, and not metaphorically, a part of himself,
so jealous is opinion of the smallest interference of law with
his absolute and exclusive control over them; more jealous than
of almost any interference with his own freedom of action: so
much less do the generality of mankind value liberty than power.
Consider, for example, the case of education. Is it not almost
a selfevident axiom, that the State should require and compel
the education, up to a certain standard, of every human being
who is born its citizen? Yet who is there that is not afraid to
recognize and assert this truth? Hardly any one indeed will deny
that it is one of the most sacred duties of the parents (or, as
law and usage now stand, the father), after summoning a human
being into the world, to give to that being an education fitting
him to perform his part well in life towards others and towards
himself. But while this is unanimously declared to be the father's
duty, scarcely anybody, in this country, will bear to hear of
obliging him to perform it. Instead of his being required to make
any exertion or sacrifice for securing education to the child,
it is left to his choice to accept it or not when it is provided
gratis! It still remains unrecognized, that to bring a child into
existence without a fair prospect of being able, not only to provide
food for its body, but instruction and training for its mind,
is a moral crime, both against the unfortunate offspring and against
society; and that if the parent does not fulfil this obligation,
the State ought to see it fulfilled, at the charge, as far as
possible, of the parent.
Were the duty of enforcing universal education once admitted,
there would be an end to the difficulties about what the State
should teach, and how it should teach, which now convert the subject
into a mere battle-field for sects and parties, causing the time
and labor which should have been spent in educating, to be wasted
in quarrelling about education. If the government would make up
its mind to require for every child a good education, it might
save itself the trouble of providing one. It might leave to parents
to obtain the education where and how they pleased, and content
itself with helping to pay the school fees of the poorer classes
of children, and defraying the entire school expenses of those
who have no one else to pay for them. The objections which are
urged with reason against State education, do not apply to the
enforcement of education by the State, but to the State's taking
upon itself to direct that education: which is a totally different
thing. That the whole or any large part of the education of the
people should be in State hands, I go as far as any one in deprecating.
All that has been said of the importance of individuality of character,
and diversity in opinions and modes of conduct, involves, as of
the same unspeakable importance, diversity of education. A general
State education is a mere contrivance for moulding people to be
exactly like one another: and as the mould in which it casts them
is that which pleases the predominant power in the government,
whether this be a monarch, a priesthood, an aristocracy, or the
majority of the existing generation, in proportion as it is efficient
and successful, it establishes a despotism over the mind, leading
by natural tendency to one over the body. An education established
and controlled by the State, should only exist, if it exist at
all, as one among many competing experiments, carried on for the
purpose of example and stimulus, to keep the others up to a certain
standard of excellence. Unless, indeed, when society in general
is in so backward a state that it could not or would not provide
for itself any proper institutions of education, unless the government
undertook the task; then, indeed, the government may, as the less
of two great evils, take upon itself the business of schools and
universities, as it may that of joint-stock companies, when private
enterprise, in a shape fitted for undertaking great works of industry
does not exist in the country. But in general, if the country
contains a sufficient number of persons qualified to provide education
under government auspices, the same persons would be able and
willing to give an equally good education on the voluntary principle,
under the assurance of remuneration afforded by a law rendering
education compulsory, combined with State aid to those unable
to defray the expense.
The instrument for enforcing the law could be no other than public
examinations, extending to all children, and beginning at an early
age. An age might be fixed at which every child must be examined,
to ascertain if he (or she) is able to read. If a child proves
unable, the father, unless he has some sufficient ground of excuse,
might be subjected to a moderate fine, to be worked out, if necessary,
by his labor, and the child might be put to school at his expense.
Once in every year the examination should be renewed, with a gradually
extending range of subjects, so as to make the universal acquisition,
and what is more, retention, of a certain minimum of general knowledge,
virtually compulsory. Beyond that minimum, there should be voluntary
examinations on all subjects, at which all who come up to a certain
standard of proficiency might claim a certificate. To prevent
the State from exercising through these arrangements, an improper
influence over opinion, the knowledge required for passing an
examination (beyond the merely instrumental parts of knowledge,
such as languages and their use) should, even in the higher class
of examinations, be confined to facts and positive science exclusively.
The examinations on religion, politics, or other disputed topics,
shouLd not turn on the truth or falsehood of opinions, but on
the matter of fact that such and such an opinion is held, on such
grounds, by such authors, or schools, or churches. Under this
system, the rising generation would be no worse off in regard
to all disputed truths, than they are at present; they would be
brought up either churchmen or dissenters as they now are, the
State merely taking care that they should be instructed churchmen,
or instructed dissenters. There would be nothing to hinder them
from being taught religion, if their parents chose, at the same
schools where they were taught other things. All attempts by the
State to bias the conclusions of its citizens on disputed subjects,
are evil; but it may very properly offer to ascertain and certify
that a person possesses the knowledge requisite to make his conclusions,
on any given subject, worth attending to. A student of philosophy
would be the better for being able to stand an examination both
in Locke and in Kant, whichever of the two he takes up with, or
even if with neither: and there is no reasonable objection to
examining an atheist in the evidences of Christianity, provided
he is not required to profess a belief in them. The examinations,
however, in the higher branches of knowledge should, I conceive,
be entirely voluntary. It would be giving too dangerous a power
to governments, were they allowed to exclude any one from professions,
even from the profession of teacher, for alleged deficiency of
qualifications: and I think, with Wilhelm von Humboldt, that degrees,
or other public certificates of scientific or professional acquirements,
should be given to all who present themselves for examination,
and stand the test; but that such certificates should confer no
advantage over competitors, other than the weight which may be
attached to their testimony by public opinion.
It is not in the matter of education only that misplaced notions
of liberty prevent moral obligations on the part of parents from
being recognized, and legal obligations from being imposed, where
there are the strongest grounds for the former always, and in
many cases for the latter also. The fact itself, of causing the
existence of a human being, is one of the most responsible actions
in the range of human life. To undertake this responsibility--to
bestow a life which may be either a curse or a blessing--unless
the being on whom it is to be bestowed will have at least the
ordinary chances of a desirable existence, is a crime against
that being. And in a country either over-peopled or threatened
with being so, to produce children, beyond a very small number,
with the effect of reducing the reward of labor by their competition,
is a serious offence against all who live by the remuneration
of their labor. The laws which, in many countries on the Continent,
forbid marriage unless the parties can show that they have the
means of supporting a family, do not exceed the legitimate powers
of the State: and whether such laws be expedient or not (a question
mainly dependent on local circumstances and feelings), they are
not objectionable as violations of liberty. Such laws are interferences
of the State to prohibit a mischievous act--an act injurious to
others, which ought to be a subject of reprobation, and social
stigma, even when it is not deemed expedient to superadd legal
punishment. Yet the current ideas of liberty, which bend so easily
to real infringements of the freedom of the individual, in things
which concern only himself, would repel the attempt to put any
restraint upon his inclinations when the consequence of their
indulgence is a life, or lives, of wretchedness and depravity
to the offspring, with manifold evils to those sufficiently within
reach to be in any way affected by their actions. When we compare
the strange respect of mankind for liberty, with their strange
want of respect for it, we might imagine that a man had an indispensable
right to do harm to others, and no right at all to please himself
without giving pain to any one.
I have reserved for the last place a large class of questions
respecting the limits of government interference, which, though
closely connected with the subject of this Essay, do not, in strictness,
belong to it. These are cases in which the reasons against interference
do not turn upon the principle of liberty: the question is not
about restraining the actions of individuals, but about helping
them: it is asked whether the government should do, or cause to
be done, something for their benefit, instead of leaving it to
be done by themselves, individually, or in voluntary combination.
The objections to government interference, when it is not such
as to involve infringement of liberty, may be of three kinds.
The first is, when the thing to be done is likely to be better
done by individuals than by the government. Speaking generally,
there is no one so fit to conduct any business, or to determine
how or by whom it shall be conducted, as those who are personally
interested in it. This principle condemns the interferences, once
so common, of the legislature, or the officers of government,
with the ordinary processes of industry. But this part of the
subject has been sufficiently enlarged upon by political economists,
and is not particularly related to the principles of this Essay.
The second objection is more nearly allied to our subject. In
many cases, though individuals may not do the particular thing
so well, on the average, as the officers of government, it is
nevertheless desirable that it should be done by them, rather
than by the government, as a means to their own mental education--a
mode of strengthening their active faculties, exercising their
judgment, and giving them a familiar knowledge of the subjects
with which they are thus left to deal. This is a principal, though
not the sole, recommendation of jury trial (in cases not political);
of free and popular local and municipal institutions; of the conduct
of industrial and philanthropic enterprises by voluntary associations.
These are not questions of liberty, and are connected with that
subject only by remote tendencies; but they are questions of development.
It belongs to a different occasion from the present to dwell on
these things as parts of national education; as being, in truth,
the peculiar training of a citizen, the practical part of the
political education of a free people, taking them out of the narrow
circle of personal and family selfishness, and accustoming them
to the comprehension of joint interests, the management of joint
concerns--habituating them to act from public or semipublic motives,
and guide their conduct by aims which unite instead of isolating
them from one another. Without these habits and powers, a free
constitution can neither be worked nor preserved, as is exemplified
by the too-often transitory nature of political freedom in countries
where it does not rest upon a sufficient basis of local liberties.
The management of purely local business by the localities, and
of the great enterprises of industry by the union of those who
voluntarily supply the pecuniary means, is further recommended
by all the advantages which have been set forth in this Essay
as belonging to individuality of development, and diversity of
modes of action. Government operations tend to be everywhere alike.
With individuals and voluntary associations, on the contrary,
there are varied experiments, and endless diversity of experience.
What the State can usefully do, is to make itself a central depository,
and active circulator and diffuser, of the experience resulting
from many trials. Its business is to enable each experimentalist
to benefit by the experiments of others, instead of tolerating
no experiments but its own.
The third, and most cogent reason for restricting the interference
of government, is the great evil of adding unnecessarily to its
power. Every function superadded to those already exercised by
the government, causes its influence over hopes and fears to be
more widely diffused, and converts, more and more, the active
and ambitious part of the public into hangers-on of the government,
or of some party which aims at becoming the government. If the
roads, the railways, the banks, the insurance offices, the great
joint-stock companies, the universities, and the public charities,
were all of them branches of the government; if, in addition,
the municipal corporations and local boards, with all that now
devolves on them, became departments of the central administration;
if the employes of all these different enterprises were appointed
and paid by the government, and looked to the government for every
rise in life; not all the freedom of the press and popular constitution
of the legislature would make this or any other country free otherwise
than in name. And the evil would be greater, the more efficiently
and scientifically the administrative machinery was constructed--the
more skilful the arrangements for obtaining the best qualified
hands and heads with which to work it. In England it has of late
been proposed that all the members of the civil service of government
should be selected by competitive examination, to obtain for those
employments the most intelligent and instructed persons procurable;
and much has been said and written for and against this proposal.
One of the arguments most insisted on by its opponents is that
the occupation of a permanent official servant of the State does
not hold out sufficient prospects of emolument and importance
to attract the highest talents, which will always be able to find
a more inviting career in the professions, or in the service of
companies and other public bodies. One would not have been surprised
if this argument had been used by the friends of the proposition,
as an answer to its principal difficulty. Coming from the opponents
it is strange enough. What is urged as an objection is the safety-valve
of the proposed system. If indeed all the high talent of the country
could be drawn into the service of the government, a proposal
tending to bring about that result might well inspire uneasiness.
If every part of the business of society which required organized
concert, or large and comprehensive views, were in the hands of
the government, and if government offices were universally filled
by the ablest men, all the enlarged culture and practised intelligence
in the country, except the purely speculative, would be concentrated
in a numerous bureaucracy, to whom alone the rest of the community
would look for all things: the multitude for direction and dictation
in all they had to do; the able and aspiring for personal advancement.
To be admitted into the ranks of this bureaucracy, and when admitted,
to rise therein, would be the sole objects of ambition. Under
this regime, not only is the outside public ill-qualified, for
want of practical experience, to criticize or check the mode of
operation of the bureaucracy, but even if the accidents of despotic
or the natural working of popular institutions occasionally raise
to the summit a ruler or rulers of reforming inclinations, no
reform can be effected which is contrary to the interest of the
bureaucracy. Such is the melancholy condition of the Russian empire,
as is shown in the accounts of those who have had sufficient opportunity
of observation. The Czar himself is powerless against the bureaucratic
body: he can send any one of them to Siberia, but he cannot govern
without them, or against their will. On every decree of his they
have a tacit veto, by merely refraining from carrying it into
effect. In countries of more advanced civilization and of a more
insurrectionary spirit the public, accustomed to expect everything
to be done for them by the State, or at least to do nothing for
themselves without asking from the State not only leave to do
it, but even how it is to be done, naturally hold the State responsible
for all evil which befalls them, and when the evil exceeds their
amount of patience, they rise against the government and make
what is called a revolution; whereupon somebody else, with or
without legitimate authority from the nation, vaults into the
seat, issues his orders to the bureaucracy, and everything goes
on much as it did before; the bureaucracy being unchanged, and
nobody else being capable of taking their place.
A very different spectacle is exhibited among a people accustomed
to transact their own business. In France, a large part of the
people having been engaged in military service, many of whom have
held at least the rank of noncommissioned officers, there are
in every popular insurrection several persons competent to take
the lead, and improvise some tolerable plan of action. What the
French are in military affairs, the Americans are in every kind
of civil business; let them be left without a government, every
body of Americans is able to improvise one, and to carry on that
or any other public business with a sufficient amount of intelligence,
order and decision. This is what every free people ought to be:
and a people capable of this is certain to be free; it will never
let itself be enslaved by any man or body of men because these
are able to seize and pull the reins of the central administration.
No bureaucracy can hope to make such a people as this do or undergo
anything that they do not like. But where everything is done through
the bureaucracy, nothing to which the bureaucracy is really adverse
can be done at all. The constitution of such countries is an organization
of the experience and practical ability of the nation, into a
disciplined body for the purpose of governing the rest; and the
more perfect that organization is in itself, the more successful
in drawing to itself and educating for itself the persons of greatest
capacity from all ranks of the community, the more complete is
the bondage of all, the members of the bureaucracy included. For
the governors are as much the slaves of their organization and
discipline, as the governed are of the governors. A Chinese mandarin
is as much the tool and creature of a despotism as the humblest
cultivator. An individual Jesuit is to the utmost degree of abasement
the slave of his order though the order itself exists for the
collective power and importance of its members.
It is not, also, to be forgotten, that the absorption of all the
principal ability of the country into the governing body is fatal,
sooner or later, to the mental activity and progressiveness of
the body itself. Banded together as they are--working a system
which, like all systems, necessarily proceeds in a great measure
by fixed rules--the official body are under the constant temptation
of sinking into indolent routine, or, if they now and then desert
that mill-horse round, of rushing into some half-examined crudity
which has struck the fancy of some leading member of the corps:
and the sole check to these closely allied, though seemingly opposite,
tendencies, the only stimulus which can keep the ability of the
body itself up to a high standard, is liability to the watchful
criticism of equal ability outside the body. It is indispensable,
therefore, that the means should exist, independently of the government,
of forming such ability, and furnishing it with the opportunities
and experience necessary for a correct judgment of great practical
affairs. If we would possess permanently a skilful and efficient
body of functionaries --above all, a body able to originate and
willing to adopt improvements; if we would not have our bureaucracy
degenerate into a pedantocracy, this body must not engross all
the occupations which form and cultivate the faculties required
for the government of mankind.
To determine the point at which evils, so formidable to human
freedom and advancement begin, or rather at which they begin to
predominate over the benefits attending the collective application
of the force of society, under its recognized chiefs, for the
removal of the obstacles which stand in the way of its well-being,
to secure as much of the advantages of centralized power and intelligence,
as can be had without turning into governmental channels too great
a proportion of the general activity, is one of the most difficult
and complicated questions in the art of government. It is, in
a great measure, a question of detail, in which many and various
considerations must be kept in view, and no absolute rule can
be laid down. But I believe that the practical principle in which
safety resides, the ideal to be kept in view, the standard by
which to test all arrangements intended for overcoming the difficulty,
may be conveyed in these words: the greatest dissemination of
power consistent with efficiency; but the greatest possible centralization
of information, and diffusion of it from the centre. Thus, in
municipal administration, there would be, as in the New England
States, a very minute division among separate officers, chosen
by the localities, of all business which is not better left to
the persons directly interested; but besides this, there would
be, in each department of local affairs, a central superintendence,
forming a branch of the general government. The organ of this
superintendence would concentrate, as in a focus, the variety
of information and experience derived from the conduct of that
branch of public business in all the localities, from everything
analogous which is done in foreign countries, and from the general
principles of political science. This central organ should have
a right to know all that is done, and its special duty should
be that of making the knowledge acquired in one place available
for others. Emancipated from the petty prejudices and narrow views
of a locality by its elevated position and comprehensive sphere
of observation, its advice would naturally carry much authority;
but its actual power, as a permanent institution, should, I conceive,
be limited to compelling the local officers to obey the laws laid
down for their guidance. In all things not provided for by general
rules, those officers should be left to their own judgment, under
responsibility to their constituents. For the violation of rules,
they should be responsible to law, and the rules themselves should
be laid down by the legislature; the central administrative authority
only watching over their execution, and if they were not properly
carried into effect, appealing, according to the nature of the
case, to the tribunal to enforce the law, or to the constituencies
to dismiss the functionaries who had not executed it according
to its spirit. Such, in its general conception, is the central
superintendence which the Poor Law Board is intended to exercise
over the administrators of the Poor Rate throughout the country.
Whatever powers the Board exercises beyond this limit, were right
and necessary in that peculiar case, for the cure of rooted habits
of mal-administration in matters deeply affecting not the localities
merely, but the whole community; since no locality has a moral
right to make itself by mismanagement a nest of pauperism, necessarily
overflowing into other localities, and impairing the moral and
physical condition of the whole laboring community. The powers
of administrative coercion and subordinate legislation possessed
by the Poor Law Board (but which, owing to the state of opinion
on the subject, are very scantily exercised by them), though perfectly
justifiable in a case of a first-rate national interest, would
be wholly out of place in the superintendence of interests purely
local. But a central organ of information and instruction for
all the localities, would be equally valuable in all departments
of administration. A government cannot have too much of the kind
of activity which does not impede, but aids and stimulates, individual
exertion and development. The mischief begins when, instead of
calling forth the activity and powers of individuals and bodies,
it substitutes its own activity for theirs; when, instead of informing,
advising, and upon occasion denouncing, it makes them work in
fetters or bids them stand aside and does their work instead of
them. The worth of a State, in the long run, is the worth of the
individuals composing it; and a State which postpones the interests
of their mental expansion and elevation, to a little more of administrative
skill or that semblance of it which practice gives, in the details
of business; a State, which dwarfs its men, in order that they
may be more docile instruments in its hands even for beneficial
purposes, will find that with small men no great thing can really
be accomplished; and that the perfection of machinery to which
it has sacrificed everything, will in the end avail it nothing,
for want of the vital power which, in order that the machine might
work more smoothly, it has preferred to banish. [End.]
This HTML document was prepared from The Internet Wiretap online
edition of ON LIBERTY by JOHN STUART MILL, Harvard Classics Volume
25, Copyright 1909 P.F. Collier & Son, Prepared by <dell@wiretap.spies.com>
About the online edition. This was scanned from the 1909 edition
and mechanically checked against a commercial copy of the text
from CDROM. Differences were corrected against the paper edition.
The text itself is thus a highly accurate rendition. The footnotes
were entered manually. This text is in the PUBLIC DOMAIN, released
September 1993.
This text is part of the Internet Modern History Sourcebook.
The Sourcebook is a collection of public domain and copy-permitted
texts for introductory level classes in modern European and World
history.
Unless otherwise indicated the specific electronic form of the
document is copyright. Permission is granted for electronic copying,
distribution in print form for educational purposes and personal
use. If you do reduplicate the document, indicate the source.
No permission is granted for commercial use of the Sourcebook.
(c)Paul Halsall Aug 1997
The Internet History Sourcebooks Project is located at the History Department of Fordham University, New York. The Internet
Medieval Sourcebook, and other medieval components of the project, are located at
the Fordham University Center
for Medieval Studies.The IHSP recognizes the contribution of Fordham University, the
Fordham University History Department, and the Fordham Center for Medieval Studies in
providing web space and server support for the project. The IHSP is a project independent of Fordham University. Although the IHSP seeks to follow all applicable copyright law, Fordham University is not
the institutional owner, and is not liable as the result of any legal action.
© Site Concept and Design: Paul Halsall created 26 Jan 1996: latest revision 15 November 2024 [CV]
|